Archive for the ‘Uncategorized’ Category

Stellungnahme der Jüdischen internationalen Opposition

2013/12/01

Medienkommuniqué / Pressemitteilung
Montréal 2008-08-16
Zur sofortigen Veröffentlichung
International
~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~

Stellungnahme der Jüdischen internationalen Opposition
Gegen einen Angriff auf Iran

Bemühungen, die Kriegstrommeln für einen Angriff auf Irans Kernkraftanlagen zu rühren, bestimmen das derzeitige Geschehen sowohl in den USA als auch in Israel. Nicht zuletzt die in der New York Times am 18.Juli veröffentlichte Auffassung des israelischen Historikers, Benny Morris, ist geeignet, jene politischen Kräfte zu stützen. Mit der vorliegenden Erklärung drückt die jüdische Opposition ihre Empörung aus, um diese entsetzlichen Vorschläge abzuwenden.

Dem Trommeln für einen Angriff auf Iran widersetzt sich nicht nur eine breite gesellschaftspolitische Opposition. Es läuft gegen die stille Diplomatie, die Iran zu ständigen Austauschbeziehungen mit der Atomenergie Agentur der Vereinten Nationen und ebenso zu wirtschaftlichen Handelsgesprächen mit den USA selbst bemühen. Israel hat sich zu einer Feuerpause verpflichtet, die – sehr zur Erleichterung für die Bevölkerungen in Israel und im Gazastreifen – nunmehr seit einem Monat anhält. In Anbetracht der Entwicklung einer politischen Atmosphäre der Vernunft und Verhandlung ist die militaristische Geisteshaltung bestrebt, Krieggründe hochzutreiben, um die Vorbedingungen für einen weiteren Krieg zu schaffen. Morris versucht, solche Vorbedingungen zu fabrizieren und argumentiert: „Sie (die Iraner, ER) werden – sei es aus ideologischen Gründen oder aus Angst vor einem nuklearen Präventivschlag der Israelis – jede von ihnen gebaute Bombe einsetzen. Darum ist ein israelischer Nuklearschlag, der die Iraner an ihren letzten Schritten zu einer Bombe hindert, wahrscheinlich. Die Alternative wäre, es zuzulassen, dass Teheran seine Bombe hat. So oder so, wäre in jedem der beiden
Fälle ein mittelöstlicher Nuklear-Holocaust vorherbestimmt.“ (http://nytimes.com/2008/07/18/opinion/18morris.html)

Die Werbung mit dem Argument der Unvermeidbarkeit, spielt auf die jüdische und israelische Erinnerung an den Nazi-Holocaust an. Damit soll jede Unterstützung für einen israelischen Militärschlag gegen den Iran mobilisiert und so eine Reaktion provoziert werden, die, indem die USA hineingezogen werden, zu einem weiteren Krieg führt. Dies ist umso beklagenswerter, als immerhin 16 Geheimdienstagenturen der USA zu dem Schluss gekommen sind, dass der Iran ein Atomwaffenprogramm nicht hat und auch in den vergangenen fünf Jahren nicht hatte.

Wir feiern den heldenhaften Mut des israelischen Atom-Informanten, Mordechai Vanunu, und unterstützen, indem wir mit unserer Stimme seine Verurteilung des illegalen Kernwaffenarsenals Israels verstärken, den Aufruf für einen atomwaffenfreien Mittleren Osten.

Die Geisteshaltung, die den Rufen nach einem gegenseitigen Vernichtungskrieg als Lösung von Sicherheitsproblemen zugrunde liegt, ist erstaunlich widersprüchlich. Nur die Erfindung einer Nazi-ähnlichen Bedrohung vermag für die Glaubwürdigkeit eines solchen Aufrufs zum Krieg herzuhalten –, was mit jener Begründung für die Besatzung vergleichbar ist, die eine palästinensische Verschwörung ausmacht, die Juden ins Meer zu treiben. Auch die Anspielung auf die iranische Ideologie (Islam) als Ursache der Konfrontation hält keiner Prüfung stand. Zumal die politische Kampfansage an Israel durch den iranischen Präsidenten, Mahmoud Ahmadinejad, selbst ungeachtet aller Falschübersetzungen – ein Aufruf zur Vernichtung nicht ist.

Wir streben Sicherheit für alle Betroffenen an, indem wir ein Recht auf Sicherheit für alle bejahen. Obgleich wir der Perspektive eines unvermeidbaren Konflikts keinen Glauben schenken, protestieren wir gegen die Hysterie der Iran-Bashers (Draufschläger), die nunmehr an ihren wiederholten Fehlstarts verzweifeln, einen weiteren unnötigen Krieg zu anzuzetteln. Der Versuch, Iran zu zwingen, den Resolutionen des UN-Sicherheitsrats zu entsprechen, ist rechtlich, diplomatisch und politisch kraftlos, solange die Vereinigten Staaten und Israel jede UN-Diplomatie und ebenso sämtliche Entscheidungen Internationalen Gerichtshofs in Sachen Palästina, durchweg ignorieren.

Wir rufen alle, die gegen einen Militärschlag auf Iran sind, Repräsentanten ihrer Regierungen anzuschreiben und zu fordern, dass der Staat Israel, anstelle der Verkündung von Kriegsdrohungen seine Atomeinrichtungen der internationalen Inspektion zugänglich macht und in gleicher Weise, wie es Iran schon getan hat, den Nichtverbreitungsvertrag von Nuklearwaffen (NPT – Non-Poliferation Treaty) unterzeichnet.

– 30 –

Further endorsements may be added by sending in a message to saalaha@fokus.name
Also available in French, German and Arabic
Listserv: jewswhospeakout@lists.riseup.net

Initiatoren:
Für weitere Informationen;

Stanley Heller http://www.TheStruggle.org mail@TheStruggle.org
New York

Prof. Dr. Fanny-Michaela Reisin
Jewish Voice for a Just Peace in Middle East – EJJP
http://www.juedische-stimme.de
mailto:mail@juedische-stimme.de
Germany

Abraham Weizfeld
saalaha@fokus.name Tel.: 514.284.66.42
Interim Administrative Secretary, Alliance of Concerned Jewish Canadians
Loze mir alle leiben mit shytvis un shulim
Montréal

Organisationen und Co-Unterzeichner (20):

Alliance of Concerned Jewish Canadians
jewish.alliance@yahoo.ca

Colorado Jews for a Just Peace
http://www.cjjp.org

European Jews for a Just Peace
National Office
We as Union Of French Jews for Peace, UJFP, totally agree with your position and response to Benny Morris about attack on Iran.
contact@ujfp.org
http://www.ujfp.org
Michele SibonyHouria Ackermann
Rudolf B’Kouche
Andre Rosevegue
Christine Birnbaum
Jacques Jedwab
Daniel Levyne
Pierre Stambul
Mireille Mendes France
Viviane Cohen

Granny Peace Brigade Philadelphia
Germantown Friends Meeting, Peace & Social Concerns

Independent Jewish Voices Montreal

International Jewish Solidarity Network
http://www.ijsn.net

Jewish Peace Fellowship
Box 271
Nyack, NY 10960-0271
USA

Jewish Voice for a Just Peace
Switzerland
http://www.jvjp.ch

Jewish Voice for Peace
http://www.jewishvoiceforpeace.org/

Jewish Voice for a Just Peace in the Middle East
(EJJP-Austria)

Jewish Voices for Peace and Justice
Sydney, Australia
we strongly endorse the petition against an attack on Iran.

Jews Against the Occupation
Sydney, Australia
http://www.jao.org.au

Jews for Boycotting Israeli Goods

Juedische Stimme für gerechten Frieden in Nahost – EJJP Deutschland e. V.

New Profile
Israel
a feminist, pluralist Israeli movement of males and females who wish to transform Israel from a militaristic society to a civil-ized one. http://www.newprofile.org

NION (Not In Our Name)
Toronto, Canada

Society for Austro-Arab Relations
Vienna

Willkommen!

Studienverband JESCHURUN, Judentum gegen Zionismus
Study Association YESHURUN, Judaism against Zionism.
http://www.bloggen.be/jesjoeroen and http://www.bloggen.be/yechouroun

Women in Black
Melbourne, Australia

Women in Black
San Francisco Bay Area in Oakland, California

Women in Black
Vienna

Co-Unterzeichner (162):
From 17 Countries

Paula Abrams-Hourani
Women in Black (Vienna) and
Jewish Voice for a Just Peace in the Middle East (EJJP-Austria)

Miriam Adams
New Mexico

Prof. Ammiel Alcalay
CUNY Graduate Center & Queens College

Marshall Ansell
Sweden

Henry Ascher, MD, PhD, Assoc. Professor
Gothenburg, Sweden

Willy Bach
QUT Masters research student
Vientiane
Lao PDR
I wish my name to be added to the list of Jews who are outraged by the reckless and callous proposal of war on Iran and call for an end to all covert attacks that are currently being conducted against Iran. To many peace scholars like myself it is obvious that the present feverish militarisation around the world has resulted from US belligerence and willingness to use military force.
I am living in the Peoples’ Democratic Republic of Laos forty years after the devastating bombing of this poor peasant society by the USAF. This should be a lesson to us all that war is a very brutal and indiscriminate instrument whose usefulness has long since past. Ask those war planners to explain their intensions to the Lao child in a remote village who just had their leg blown off by a cluster bomblet and is now too far from medical attention and could die from a tropical infection.

Tsela Barr
Madison Chapter of Jewish Voice for Peace

Abigail B. Bakan, Ph.D., Queen’s University
Canada

Sonia Baku
Jewish Voice for Peace
Madison Wisconsin

Andrew Berman
Peace Activist and Veteran
Minneapolis
Please add my name as an endorser of the statement in response to the despicable stance of Benny Morris. This mindset, tragically seen as an acceptable political stance by many must not go unchanged, particularly in Jewish communities worldwide.

Judith Bernstein
Jewish-Palestinian Dialogue Group Munich

Murray & Marcia Bernstein
Brooklyn, NY

Shelley Berlowitz
Jewish Voice for a Just Peace
Switzerland

Jude Binder
artist, teacher
West Virginia, USA

Rudolf Bkouche
vice-président, l’Union Juive Française pour la Paix

Shmiel Mordche Borreman
Yeshurun Judaism against Zionism
Antwerp, Belgium
http://www.bloggen.be/jesjoeren
http://www.bloggen.be/yechouroun

Hanna Braun
As a former Israeli who has renounced my nationality because I do not wish to be a citizen of such a barbaric and increasingly fascist state, I cannot but endorse your struggle against the taints and threats delivered to you by nations themselves non-democratic, war-mongering and corrupt. Unless we take a different stance and put all of humanity as important and deserving as Israel, we are doomed to a terrible bloodletting.

Lenni Brenner
Author
New York

Mark Robert Brill
As a Jewish Canadian (and inhabitant of the same planet as any and all who may read this), I
Wholeheartedly endorse the statement in opposition to the Benny Morris article which appeared in the New York Times urging an attack on Iran.
Neither as a Jew, nor a human being living in this age of myriad pressing concerns which threaten the existence of our species, can I condone the insanity of the current policy of the present United States & Israeli administrations which at least states as its belief that the Iranian nuclear program is a threat to world security. (Though I must credit the authors of those policies to be intelligent enough to know full well the dishonesty of such a stated belief so therefore must further condemn them for such cynical manipulation).
In fact, the by far greater threat to world security is and has been for some time now the actions of those above-named states.

Judith Butler
Berkeley, California

Edith Cacciatore
member of 14 Friends of Palestine
Novato, CA
USA

Paola Canarutto
physician
Italy

Lorenzo A. Canizares
Harrisburg, PA
Union Organizer

Smadar Carmon
Toronto, Canada

Prof. Noam Chomsky
MIT, Cambridge MA

James Cohen
Dept. of Political Science
Université de Paris VIII (France)

Viviane Cohen
Woman in Black, Paris France
secretaire nationale of the UJFP.
I endorse your statement against war on Iran . Definitively.

Sylvia Cohen
UK

Stephen Conroy, B. Com.
Montreal, Canada

Howard Cort
Jewish Voice for Peace/Chicago & Arab Jewish Partnership for Peace and Justice

Mark Cramer
Professor Université Paris-Jussieu and Sciences-Po (Paris)

Mike Cushman
Secretary LSE University and Colleges Union Branch (personal capacity)

Professor Suri Dalir

Michael T. Darwyne

Uri Davis (Dr)
MAIAP: Movement Against Israeli Apartheid in Palestine
http://www.maiap.org
Sakhnin, Palestine, 20173
Israel P O Box 99

Richard Lee Deaton, Ph.D., LL.B.
Ottawa, Canada

James Deutsch, M.D., Ph.D.
Judith Deutsch, M.S.W.

prof. dr. Hans Dieleman
Professor in the Autonomous University of Mexico-City (UACM)
Member of staff of the Faculty of Social Sciences, Erasmus University Rotterdam (EUR), the Netherlands

Esty Dinur
Journalist, Israeli and US citizen
Madison, WI, USA

Fritz Edlinger
Secretary General of the Society for Austro-Arab Relations
Vienna

Michael Ellman
Solicitor (attorney)
London, England

Jean M. Entine
Interim Chair Jewish Voice for Peace
USA

Prof. Avishai Ehrlich
International Relations dept.
University of Nicosia Cyprus.

Marla Erlien,
Visions of Peace and Justice in Israel/ Palestine
Boston

Malkah B. Feldman
All land is holy. All people are chosen.

Dror Feiler
Composer, musician, artist
Chairman, European Jews for a Just Peace (www.ejjp.org)
Stockholm, Sweden

Pnina Feiler
Reg. nurse
Israel

Tigran Feiler
Journalist
Sweden

Frank Fisher
moderator http://groups.yahoo.com/group/JustPeaceUK/

Deborah Fink
Jews for Boycotting Israeli Goods

Alexei Folger
Jewish Voice for Peace
San Francisco, CA, USA

Joel Frangquist
San Francisco, CA
Member of Jewish Voice for Peace, Bay Area chapter

Ruth Fruchtman
Writer, Berlin

Racheli Gai
Tucson Women in Black

Miriam Garfinkle M.D.

Roni Gechtman, Ph.D.
Assistant Professor
Department of History
Mount Saint Vincent University
Halifax, Nova Scotia, Canada

Jerry Geffner, MSW
Social Worker,
Oakland, California

Tsilli Goldenberg
Jerusalem Israel

Sheila Goldmacher,
Member, Bay Area Women in Black Study Group

Sherna Berger Gluck
Professor Emerita, California State University Long Beach USA

Sue Goldstein
Toronto
Women in Solidarity with Palestine

Julius Gordon
Tucson, AZ
Please add my name to the list of violent dissenters with Benny Morris, who proposes the start of a nuclear war in the Middle East. Based on his NY times article it appears that Prof. Morris, who at one time was considered a valuable scholar in Middle East history, has suffered a dissociative disorder. How else to explain the patent lies (no intelligence service in the world..) that a rational historian would never allow to be printed under his name.

Jepke Goudsmit
co-director Kinetic Energy Theatre Company
Sydney Australia
Dialogue and reconciliation, these are the action words which may lead to peace in the middle east.

Tony Greenstein

Francoise J. Gross
Suffern, NY

Robert B. Gross
Suffern N.Y.

Batja P. Guggenheim- Ami
St.Gallen Switzerland
&
Chanan H. Guggenheim-Ami
St. Gallen Switzerland
Members of the Israel- Palestinian Dialogue Group ‘Olivenzweig’ St. Gall CH

Freda Guttman
artist, activist

Evelyn Haas [ oldleft@hotmail.com ]

Jim Haber
Jewish Voice for Peace
Coordinator of Nevada Desert Experience
(anti-nuclear organization in Las Vegas, near the Nevada Test Site)
Las Vegas, NV and San Francisco, CA

Abe Hayeem
Architects and Planners for Justice in Palestine

Adam M. Helfgott
Substitute Teacher, Connecticut, USA

Jacques Hersh
Denmark

Dr. Annette Herskovits
Writer, California, USA

Fred Hirsch
Executive Board Member Plumbers and Fitters Local 393, Delegate to the South Bay AFL-CIO Labor Council, Delegate to the Santa Clara and San Benito Counties Building and Construction Trades Council
I endorse the statement wholeheartedly.
Benny Morris thinks the unthinkable. His article justifying a nuclear strike against Iran speaks the unspeakable. Such an action could and probably would open humanity’s door to the abyss – a monstrous step toward the end of human viability on Earth.
Shame on the New York Times for admitting such barbarity into the public discussion as normal discourse.
Israel’s unchecked development of nuclear weapons, with the help of apartheid South Africa, was an affront our legacy as Jews – a sharp stick in the eye to the population of the planet. Weapons of mass destruction indeed!
Any nuclear threat today is despicable.

Louis Hirsch
Chicago, Illinois

Dr. Tikva Honig-Parnass
Jerusalem

Jake Javanshir
I endorse your stand of no attack on Iran. I am an Iranian Jew, living in Canada. If anyone should be stoped of aggression, it’s Israel not Iran.

Dan Judelson
Secretary , European Jews for a Just Peace

miriam julkowski
storrs, CT

Jenny Kastner
Toronto, Canada

Gilda Katz
MSW, RSW, Toronto

Dr. Kate P. Katzenstein-Leiterer
Member of board of the Juedische Stimme für gerechten Frieden in Nahost – EJJP Deutschland
Executive committee member of EJJP

Maxine Kaufman-Lacusta
citizen of Canada and Israel

Mira Khazzam
Montreal, Canada

Alisa Klein
Israeli and U.S. Citizen

Dr. Anton Kuerti, O.C.
20 Linden St.
Toronto ON
Canada
I applaud this initiative; it is the height of perverted insolence for the countries who have the bomb – and especially the one that has used it – to try to dictate who else may have it. Unfortunately for the prospects of planetary survival, the bullying and aggressive behaviour of the U.S. and its clients make countries like Iran observe Iraq and North Korea, and conclude that the only way to prevent being catastrophically destroyed is to become a nuclear power.
http://www.jwentworth.com/kuerti/

Jason Kunin
Toronto

Rebekah Levin
Oak Park, IL

Joseph Levine
Dept. of Philosophy
Univ. of Mass
Amherst, MA

Abby Lippman, PhD, Professor
Montreal, Quebec

Antony Loewenstein
Sydney, Australia, journalist/author

Leslie Lomas
Colorado Jews for a Just Peace

Moshé Machover
London, UK

Dr Sabetai Matsas MD
Athens, Greece

Hilda Meers
Writer
member of Scottish Jews for a Just Peace,
Aberdeen Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament,
Grampian Senior Citizens Forum

Peter Melvyn
Vienna, Austria
Jewish Voice for a Just Peace in Neareast

Brigitte Meyer
Jewish-Palestinian Dialogue Group St.Gallen, Switzerland
I fully support the content and spirit of this statement. Real security can only come from peace.

Hajo G. Meyer, Ph.D.
Heiloo, the Netherlands
German born 1924, Auschwitz survivor during 10 months.
Physicist, author of The End of Judaism and a book in German on historic forces.
The beat of the drums of war depicting Iran as a real threat is ridiculous but extremely dangerous. It reminds me of the threat of the Polish army against Germany in 1939.

Dorinda Moreno
Fuerza Mundial Collaborative

Robert Naiman
Just Foreign Policy
Urbana, IL USA
http://www.justforeignpolicy.org

Dorothy Naor Ph.D.
Israel Naor
Israel
My spouse and I both endorse the statement and fervently hope that reason rather than emotions and war profiteering will hold sway.

Diana Neslen
United Kingdom

Joan Nestle
Melbourne, Australia,
co-founder of the Lesbian Herstory Archives

Alex Nissen
Senior Educator / Coordinator
Israeli/Australian
Women in Black Melbourne

Prof. Judith Norman
Jewish Peace News

Sara Norman
Jewish Voice for Peace
San Francisco, CA

Prof. Bertell Ollman
Dept. of Politics, NYU
New York, New York, USA.

Karin Pally
Women in Black-Los Angeles

Ilan Pappe
U. of Exeter, England

Jean Pauline
Oakland, California
Bay Area Women in Black

Nick Paretsky, Ph.D.
health care worker
Columbia, Missouri

Daniel Pines

Karen Platt
Jewish Voice for Peace
Albany, CA

Laurie Polster
Jewish Voice for Peace/Bay Area
Oakland, CA

Murray Polner
Jewish Peace Fellowship
Nyack, NY
USA

Natalie Polonsky LaRoche
Toronto
Member: CUPE 79,
Alliance of Concerned Jewish Canadians

Vivienne Porzsolt
Jews Against the Occupation
Sydney, Australia

Naomi Rankin
I fully support the content and spirit of this statement. As a Jewish Canadian with cousins in Israel, I am interested in real security for Israel, and that can come only from peace.

Roland Rance
Jews Against Zionism
London

Bruce Robbins
Columbia University

Stewart M. Robinson
retired Prof of Mathematics

Professor Jonathan Rosenhead
Secretary, British Committee for the Universities of Palestine (BRICUP)

Prof Andrew N. Rubin
Georgetown University
Washington, DC

Molly Rush
PUSH PA. United for SinglePayer HealthCare
Health Care for All PA
http://www.healthcare4allPA.org

Aram Saroyan
Los Angeles, CA
http://www.aramsaroyan.com

Margot F Salom (BA Soc Work, M Phil)
Palestinian & Jewish Unity for Justice & Peace
Stop this madness – What has happened to Jewish ethics?

Shay Salomon
Tucson, Arizona

Carol Sanders
Berkeley, California
Member of Jewish Voice for Peace

Marlena Santoyo
Philadelphia, PA, USA &
member of Jewish Voice for Peace

Yom Shamash
Jews for a Just Peace
Vancouver, Canada

Cindy Shamban
Berkeley, CA
affiliation: Jewish Voice for Peace

Sarah Shartal (Levinthal)
Toronto Canada
Over 30 years ago I refuse to serve as a soldier in the Gaza strip. At that time Israel’s government argued that only forceful military action would keep Israel’s safe. 30 years later; after many thousands of people have died in Israel and Palestine, they are again saying that only forceful military action can keep Israel’s safe. It has never been true. Pease comes from dialog and negotiation, bombs produced more bombs. Bombing nuclear facilities will poison all countries of the Middle East for hundreds of generations.

Avi Shlaim, FBA
Professor of International Relations
St Antony’s College
Oxford

Rich Siegel
Musician, Advisory Board Deir Yassin Remembered
Teaneck, NJ USA
http://www.deiryassin.org

Andy Silver
Cary, NC
July 27 letter to the Raleigh News & Observer. It was not published.
America is no place for satire. The New Yorker Obama cartoon went over like a John Kerry joke. Now some are responding seriously to the column by Benny Morris, “Soon, strike on Iran” (N&O, July 20), which presented a case for another pre-emptive war with the cogency with which Jonathan Swift proposed that Irish poverty be relieved by devouring babies.
Morris’s proposal is as insane and as devoid of humanity as Swift’s “modest proposal.” It should convince any sane person of the insanity of attacking Iran.
I doubt, however, the sanity of all discussion of Iran’s nuclear threat. The existing nuclear threat in the Middle East comes from Israel. Israel’s arsenal is controlled by the same Israeli government that dropped a million cluster bombs in southern Lebanon only for the purpose of killing and maiming farm families that wished to return to their land. Israel’s bombs provide the motive for surrounding nations to seek nuclear weapons. The only way to prevent nuclear proliferation in the Middle East is to create a nuclear arms free zone. In return for Israel’s dismantling its nuclear arsenal and agreeing to strict inspections by the IAEA, other countries in the region should make similar commitments.

Gary and Annemarie Slipper
Mexico
hoping that reasonable minds will prevail

Miriam Victory Spiegel
Zürich, Switzerland and New York City

Jayne Lyn Stahl

Jonatan Stanczak
The Freedom Theatre, Jenin refugee Camp

Marge Sussman
Jewish Voice for Peace

Cy & Lois Swartz
Bubbes & Zaydes (Grandparents) for Peace in the Middle East
PO Box 56293 Philadelphia Pa., 19130 USA

Merlin Swartz, Bedford, MA USA
Ruth Tenne
Israeli peace activist
I fully endorse the statement against any attack attack on Iran which is illegal and constitutes a war crime according to international law.

Lea Tsemel
Human Rights Attorney
Jerusalem

Roger Tucker
http://one-state.net

Richard Wagman
Honorary President
French Jewish Peace Union
Union juive française pour la paix (UJFP)
(affiliated to EJJP – European Jews for a Just Peace)

Richard Wark, PhD.
Durham, North Carolina

Michael Warschawski
Activist
Jerusalem

Jochi Weil-Goldstein
Zurich
Responsible for Project at medico international schweiz, formerly Centrale Sanitaire Suisse CSS Zürich http://www.medicointernational.ch
Co-Founder and Activist of the Olive Oil Campaign in Switzerland http://www.olivenoel-palaestina.ch

Jess Weinberg
Las Cruces, New Mexico

Judith Weisman,
Toronto, Canada

Suzanne Weiss
Holocaust survivor
Not In Our Name (NION) Jewish Voices Opposing Zionism
Toronto

Evan Weissman
Denver, CO USA
Playwright and Nonviolence Teacher

Célie Weizfeld Castelijn
Montréal Kébèk

Dr. Samuel Wiener
Jewish Voice for a Just Peace
Switzerland

Marcy Winograd
Los Angeles, CA

Tamar Yaron
Canada, Israel

Roger van Zwanenberg (Dr)
Chair & Commissioning Editor
Pluto Press

Endorsers general (11):
From 5 countries

Moji Agha
Founder/Director
Project on Culture and Conflict, U. of Arizona
International Institute to study Climate Change in the Islamic World (IISCCIW)
http://www.iiscciw.org

Suzanne Radford
JEFarrow
Parallel Perspectives
http://www.gnostics.com
We heartily endorse the open-minded opinions & views expressed in your Opposition statement re. War against Iran.

Robert Berger
I have to honor every Jew who is against a attack against Iran.
I believe the Iranians claim that they do not want to have any nukes.
Remember the Fatwa against the nuclear bomb.
If the Iranians are building a nuclear bomb they would betray their religion and their word.
If the outside world let the Iranians in peace with time their religious extremism will soften and they may even become friends.
If their economical and political system is not good then that’s only the Iranians business they will have to live with it.
To force the whole world to accept the American economical system is like the farmer with one crop every year in the beginning it is good but a crisis comes and everything collapses.

J Bowne
MiddleEastPeaceForum
Ashland, OR USA

Dr Stella Cornelius, AO, OBE
Director, Conflict Resolution Network
AUSTRALIA
Website: http://www.crnhq.org

Trevor Goodger-Hill
Citizen of the World
Trottier Mills, Quebec
Present-day war is caused by nation states, in the interest of the ruling class, fighting over land, markets and power. The temporary solution of Israel is to create a unitary secular state consisting of all of Palestine.
The permanent solution is to abolish the nation state and replace world-wide capitalism with a cooperative world society as stated in the credo of Citizens of the World

Tamzin Jans
Brussels, Belgium (in Libya)

William James Martin
Department of Mathematics
University of New Orleans
I wonder how sane Benny Morris is. Benny Morris does not know Arabic, obviously he does not know Farsi. Why would a world class historian stake his believe on what any Farsi expert could tell him was a mistranslation of a statement by Ahmadinejad? It may be that it is paranoia that sustains the state of Israel. The state of Israel seems to thrive on persecution, imagined in most cases. The claim that Arabs want to throw the Jews into the sea, is the creation of David Ben Gurion, and not that of a significant Arab leader. I favour a one state solution. Any state which has to keep 4 million human beings in an outdoor prison, treated like cattle for 40 years, and deprived of basic human rights on order to maintain itself as a state for a privileged racial or ethnic group has no moral right to exists. Add to this that Israel ethnically cleansed three quarter of a million people in 1948, an ethnic cleansing which has never ceased. Ethnic cleansing is universally recognized as a war crime.
Anna McCormack
Da Nang
Vietnam

Chengiah Ragaven
Ph.D(ABD) (McGill), MA.(Oxon), MA.(Sussex), MA.(UKZN), B.Ed (London)
Faculty-International Studies/Africana Center Central Connecticut State University Research Fellow-Simone de Beauvoir Concordia University-Montreal, Canada
Former Political Prisoner in South Africa
Please add my name to the list.
Any escalation of war only serves the escalation of 21st century barbarism

Further endorsements may be added by sending in a message to saalaha@fokus.name
Also available in French, German and Arabic
Listserv: jewswhospeakout@lists.riseup.net

~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~

National-Cultural Autonomy and Isra’tine

2013/11/30

National-Cultural Autonomy and Isratine
By Abraham Weizfeld
04-2009

Abstract

The Nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. While the incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism”, national identity per se is associated with Civil Society. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Palestine/Israel or the impasse of Québécois/se national-identity, in the context of the Dominion of Canada.

The tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations.

1) Introduction

National-Cultural Autonomy and Isratine

By Abraham Weizfeld
2009

an examination of the two-state proposition to determine if it has any potential for the resolution of the fundamental social contradiction between two Peoples. The 2-State notion accommodates Zionist and its State by the adoption of the Nation-State as a paradigm for a treaty between two so-called sovereign powers. Each considers the other independent even though there is a significant over layering of population. The coincidence of nation and State is in actuality a fiction based upon ideological necessity alone.

Bauer p.37 , 39

Considering the social contradiction of two national cultures present in equivalent numbers, the prospect of a democratic solution is limited by the refusal of either national population to allow itself to be relegated to the status of a permanent minority.

In the light of the dispersal of the two national populations in diverse territorial regions of the territory originally know as Kana’an, the feasibility of a territorial separation as is proposed in the ‘Two-State solution’ is nil.

The deconstruction of the Zionist Nation-State together with the Bantuization of the Occupied Palestinian Territories recognizes the existence of the two populations each with their own distinct political culture. In terms of first principles it is the natural tendency of each of the national populations to resort to the fundamental constitution of their Peoples’ assemblies to take into consideration the constitutional nature of the unified society that each are obliged to live with. As in the 35 National Assemblies of the Sinai experience with Moses where civil society expressed itself without a State and without a territory, and the emerging Palestinian civil society of the resistance, there is the basis for the reciprocal existence of each national civil society in autonomous and integrated cohabitation.

Bauer points out that the centralist-atomist constitutional democracy of Liberalism necessarily pits one nation against another while they each seek power in the State apparatus to promote their own nation’s needs and/or privileges.

“Every nation needs power, which means the possibility of having its way, of satisfying its needs. But only centralist-atomist regulation obliges the nations to acquire this power by struggling for direct influence within the state, obliges them to struggle for power. The power of the nations to satisfy their cultural needs must be legally guaranteed if the population is no longer to be forced to divide into national parties, if conflict between national groups is not to make the class struggle impossible.” p. 252 (See Tony Greenstein’s work on the Histradrut)

The Zionist version of Apartheid sought the segregation of Palestinian workers from the Israeli Jewish national community seemingly as a means of ensuring Jewish self-determination while denying Palestinian self-determination and social existence. This is the consequence of the centralist-atomist paradigm which opens the intra-national struggle under the domination of the Zionist State. The anti-Zionist solution must then avoid the same paradigm and ensure the fulfillment of each national community’s interest without denying another those very same rights by the use of an artificial majority of votes. Ethnic cleansing has brought about the Jabotinsky model of development where the Palestinian population is limited to 20% of the population. In actuality, the two national populations are about equal in numbers now in the actual territories occupied by the Zionist State and the inevitability of Palestinian population growth makes a fragile thing of the manipulated Israeli Jewish majority.

To take the matter into consideration in the context of a unified society along the lines of the Isratine concept there would actually be a relative minority of the Jewish population which would co-habitat when the Palestinian refugee population is included, compromising an additional five million Palestinians.

In order to make the context of a unified society appealing to both national communities and so bring about its feasibility by; 1) removing the apparent need for national conflict and 2) allowing for the power of a united working class to take its effect. Such a programme would bring the national relations into reciprocity where they are not forced to struggle for state power and by which the development toward democracy does not threaten the power of any nation. It becomes evident that there is a necessity for the implementation of democracy along the lines of a direct democracy in a parallel fashion where each nation retains its collective interests while securing the collective interests of any other nation in the common society.

The constitutional programme implied by such a sense of common collective interest is only conceivable with the prospect of workers’ control in a necessarily socialist political economy. This precondition was announced in Bauer by reference to,

The eyes of the proletariat thus necessarily turn to the other conceivable form of regulating the relationships of nations to the state, that form which Rudolf Springer (Renner) has termed the organic conception. Each nation should independently satisfy its own national cultural needs, should govern itself; the state should limit itself to the protection of those interests which are a matter of indifference in national terms, but are common to all nations. Thus, national autonomy, the self-determination of nations, necessarily becomes the constitution program of the working class of all nations within the multinational state.

The dominion of the Nation-State has dominated The Modern Age with its culmination during the 20th Century with its 125 million lost lives during those various wars, including the mass annihilation by nuclear bomb, not to speak of the industrial genocide of Nazism .

The fixed idea of the Nation-State continues the monarchist conceptualization that had begun with the deification of the head of State/Empire. The emancipation of the Nations was brought about within the confines of the European State-Monarchy when the moral imperative of a national religion provided the common consciousness needed for each social entity to form the Nation-State out of the turmoil of the Reformation.

Considering that we are now faced with a national-State that names itself Israel and occupied a territory within which only half the resident population is provided with full citizenship; considering that the proposed two-state solution in whatever form defers to the current parcelization of the OPT (Occupied Palestinian Territories) into Bantustan territories or, as the previously named ‘Pale of Settlement’; considering that there is considerable intermingling of populations; one is obliged to dissociate territory from self-determination and so abandon the notion of the Nation-State and form-up a society based on a consensual decision-making process that begins with the negotiations between the two parties for a peace treaty as proposed by all Palestinian factions and continually undermined by the State authorities of Israel. Resorting to the Jewish population of Israel as such is the logical consequence of such an impasse. An appeal to both the Israel Jewish Arab population of Sephardim and Mizrahim on the basis of the mutual recognition as Arab, together with the prospect of the mutual recognition of each national identity in reciprocity. Considering the massive rejection of the Millet status as practised in the Ottoman Islamic Ummah, the status of a minority national identity is considered obsolete by both the Jewish Arabs and the Israeli Palestinian communities.

Accordingly there is the necessity for a strategy programme that surpasses each of the preceding constitutional arrangement that have been imposed by one form of state or another. The formulations for a bi-national State are suspect in that such a conception was also behind the verbiage of the South African Apartheid regime with advocated a ‘Separate but equal’ conception with was moreso a merit system which awarded equality by the definition provided by one party alone. Such a definition of rights was subject to the ideological rationale behind the State in the first place. Any State would have its ideological rationale. To remove the discussion from that State superstructure one has to consider constitutional formats such as a Confederation or Federalism in the context of Civil Society and not the State, if it were to be reciprocal and operate on the basis of consensual understanding.

Such a conception was attempted by Otto Bauer in the context of the Austro-Hungarian Empire prior to European World War I. While limited in its appreciation of social identity as a nation and to the significance of national oppression, Bauer projected the integration of society by the mutual recognition of national-cultural identity. The perspective of Otto Bauer beholden to the Austro-Hungarian Empire sought to create a social bond beyond the particular national culture to provide for a cohesive inter-national society.

The conception of National-Cultural Autonomy is originally found in the conceptions of the Jewish Workers’ Bund and its history beginning in 1897 together with the Wimberg Austrian Social-Democratic Party congress which provided for internal national-cultural autonomy . Both sources are of interest in terms of the social infrastructure that is sought by each of the national identities that conceives of itself as such.

2) Otto Bauer and Austrian Social-Democracy

In multiculturalism the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is oftentimes associated with a territory or province within the context of a State. The proposition by Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire was concerned with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred in the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances, national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other. The lack of recognition of the various national minorities was a fundamental flaw in the perpetuation of the State. As such, the nationalities question was given a priority in spite of the centralizing dynamic of the State apparatus. The practice of majoritarianism was in itself central to the monolithic State operation and yet inimical to it survival.

Each nation would believe its own minorities to be disadvantaged and would see itself as able to combat the oppression of its own minorities by taking revenge on the minorities of other nations within its region. Thus, national self-determination on the basis of the territorial principle would simple provoke renewed national struggles.
For this reason alone, the territorial principle cannot satisfy the demands of the working class.

The need to overcome the majority criterion rooted in the dominant national culture in many cases was proposed to be overcome by the constitutional guarantee for collective representation of “sovereign corporations”. Such social formations exist in and of themselves without the concurrent definition of any majority and is intended to overcome the paradigm of majorities and minorities. As such the bi-national proposal for Israel/Palestine is overcome in favour of the autonomy of each nation to allow for the integration of the Palestinian refugee population without giving rise to a permanent minority without power of the Israeli Jewish community. This allows for a consensual appreciation of an integrated society.

The topology of society became a dynamic soup of varying social currents and cultures all intertwined into a given geography but without a specific territory of its own. Such cosmopolitanism on a grand scale was the means by which loyalty to the State was to be achieved when the State became the guarantor of the national cultural autonomy that was held dearest by each particular culture.

In its pure form, the aim of the personality principle is to constitute the nation not as a territorial corporation, but as an association of persons.

The precedent provided by the Islamic Ummah of the Turkish Empire gave rise to the Millet system of national autonomy extended to non-territorial social entities. The mosaic of autonomous cultures was an internally stable form of governance. Although the Dimmuni status of such minorities was recognized, protected and taxed for the effort, as if such status was provisional and secondary, it nonetheless inspired respect on the part of Otto Bauer.

The democratic federation of national communities incubated by Otto Bauer challenged the notion of sovereignty in a unitary and indivisible construct replicated internationally by the principle of the self-determination of nations which require their nation-state and that such national-states only recognize other such nation-states. At the same time Bauer sought the perpetuation of the bourgeois Austro-Hungarian Empire. The limitations of liberal democracies are demonstrated by the failure of Bauer to implement his programme in the Austrian context. The incompatibility of the European Nation-State and the relief offered by national-cultural autonomy is a consequence of the hegemony of the dominant nation. The secondary nature of national-cultural autonomy as in the Millet system offered a suspect remedy to a bourgeois national class compact. The rejection of such autonomy is the prelude to the collapse of that nation-state. Either conception of society is, in consequence, the failure of a class dominated state since the dynamic of a state superstructure is to build itself on the social unit that most closely resembles itself. This state has rested upon the national bourgeois class as a nation-state and in the absence of the bourgeoisie is fated to tolerate the political party that has formed itself into a pre-state body that is itself a replication of the national stratum that it seeks to direct. The monopolisation of the State power is dependent upon the hegemony of the dominant strata of the population, that being either the national bourgeoisie or the national proletariat. The same problem applies in both cases. It is not the class in control that determines the prominence of the social project but the historic social formation that has dominated the political project previously. The viability of the project is put into doubt equally by the fact that not all social formations are represented, neither the minority nationalities nor the subordinate gender strata within each of the nations involved as well.

The effort to reconcile the various nations coexisting in the same political superstructure is a matter of accommodation of the minority or non-dominant nationalities by means of a sort of autonomy. While it has been found that the autonomy granted the subordinated social formations such as the Québécois or the Palestinians is insufficient when limited to a provincial or a non-sovereign Authority, it may also be found that the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is itself incompatible with the nature of the sponsoring state in the first place.

By consequence, the various national liberation struggles of the 20th Century have sought to fit within the paradigm of what has become defined as a nation. The formation of a nation-state is oftentimes confronted by the presence of further nationalities which contest the hegemony of that particular nation asserting its particular sovereignty. The exercise of self-determination in such circumstances becomes ethnic cleansing with the goal of building a predominant national charter to the social composition. This is in itself the replication of the original problem for which the nation has sought to escape by building its own nation-state. The attempts to induce a social assimilation by economic stimulation have failed on numerous occasions demonstrating that economic determinism or economic liberalism does not make a worker without a national-cultural identity.

The aspiration to national conquest within the multinational state is therefore based on good reasons as long as the nations conduct their struggle in terms of the pursuit of state power. The situation alters completely as soon as the atomist-centralist is replaced by the organic regulation of national relations. Here the state has nothing to offer the nations as totalities, and the power struggle of the nations therefore no longer has any point. The nation is legally assured the power it requires; it no longer struggles to obtain it. In this case, the nation therefore no longer needs to pursue national conquest.

In the Palestine/Israel context, the PLO (Palestine Liberation Organization) initially proposed a democratic secular state that is based on the paradigm of the atomist-centralist state. This is expressed as either a liberal-secular democracy, a bi-national state, or a multicultural democracy. This list of paradigms includes the proposal for a “regional federal union” by Moshé Machover.

While the contradiction of the nature of national-cultural autonomy with respect to the State leads us out of the context of the State, the alternative remains unresolved. In default of which, the tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations. Ultimately, the separation of ethnicities is recognized as an impossibility, or a war crime against human rights.

The concretisation of such constitutional proposals remains limited by its association with the nation-state concept and the territory to which it takes itself to belonging. The dissociation of nation and territory is fundamental to resolving the contradiction between the counterpoised senses of national self-determination. Taking political culture as the fundamental aspect of national-identity rather than a particular territory allows for the independence of national identity from territory alone. National divisions are removed in respect to the sovereignty over territory to become the independence of the national culture, and in consequence the People. While the modern national-state is fostered by a bourgeoisie class sense of order which prioritizes the economic dominance of its inheritance, culture does not require a territory upon which to build an economy, which leaves aside a People, as such.

The manner by which a People expresses its identity in self-determination is by the constitutional provisions for national autonomy which apply to the members of that community rather to the inhabitants of a particular tract of real estate. This socialization of the territory is accomplished in the name of all the nations concerned without separation into Apartheid-like conditions. By the provisions of national-cultural autonomy the organic consensus of each Nation is expressed in their own polity formed up as Civil Society and coalesced into a Constituent Assembly. The General Constituent Assembly being the federative body. Matters of national-culture are carried by each of the constituent assemblies organized on the basis of the civil society organizations. Those matters of common concern are held in consideration by the general assembly. Ongoing matters of common concern are implemented by tripartheid commissions, such as judicial bodies and the self-defence apparatus. In the principle of reciprocal national relations in a common society for example there would be a panel of judges comprised of a judge from each national culture together with their common choice for the third.

Otto Bauer provides a vivid illustration of Autonomy as auto-determination;

We have seen that socialism will necessarily lead to the realization of the principle of nationality. However, in that socialist society will construct a federative state above the national polities into which the polities are in tern gradually incorporated, the principle of nationality will change into national autonomy, the principle of nationality as the rule oft e formation of the sate into the principle of nationality as the rule of the constitution of the state. The socialist principle of nationality is the superior unity of the principle of nationality and national autonomy. … it will be just as different from the centralist atomist organization of our states as the equally diversely structured society of the Middle Ages…. The totality organized into national polities called upon to independently develop and freely enjoy their national cultures – this is the socialist principle of nationality

The introduction of the concept of national-cultural autonomy then posits the nullification of the nation-state itself, as an expression of sovereignty. The intensity of this contradiction tends to increase with the continuing waves of human migration which have never abated since the emergence of the human species from east-central Africa beginning some 200,000 years ago.

While Bauer limited national-cultural autonomy to national minorities, in effect the other of two or more nations cohabiting; it is in its reciprocal application that the feasibility of a no-state strategy is conceived. The criterion of a majority is abandoned as being superficial, arbitrary and an abrogation of minority rights. Considering that all members of society are in a minority of one sort or another, this aspect addresses the fundamental nature of democratic theory. In the practice of national-cultural autonomy the pattern of national domination by majoritarianism is annulled. Each Nation constitutes its own majority or preferably, their own consensus. This is of course the negation of liberal democracy as well, together with the social forces that promote it.

Nimni provides the synopsis of the irreducibility of the forms of the social by arguing “that the process of common reciprocal interaction lived in a permanent reciprocal relations generates a national community and expresses itself in an intersubjective bond that shapes each ‘individual National identity’ ”. This social morphology (sozial Formenlehre) is linked to the will (Wille) expressed by Neitzsche in the sense that “will is the societalized expression of human existence … ‘national apperception’ “ often expressed as national character or the collective will (as in Gramsci) and the ‘community of fate’ (Schicksalsgemeinschaft) (in Nietzsche) . Kant’s Third Analogy of Experience, the principle of community that “All substances so far as they coexist, stand in thoroughgoing community, that is, in mutual interaction.”

The dichotomy of civic and ethnic identity is contextualized by the State and social multiculturalism, respectively. Consequently, the nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. The incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism” that is integral to the antinomy. At its origin, the Hegelian concept of the Nation-State presented national identity as the State rather than in its social Form of multiculturalism. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Israel/Palestine.

The presumption that the national identity of a people dissolves under the economic determinism of the proletarian condition does not stand up to the historical record and is subjected to the evaluation by Nimni as well that, “Whenever the capitalist mode of production becomes dominate, an industrial proletariat emerges that experiences similar conditions of exploitation under capitalism regardless of national location. But in this case it is the similarity of fate and not the community of fate that generates the common character.” This “existence of a dynamic process of interaction” is referred to as ‘commercium’ by Kant.

The three schools of national theory thus are defined as:
1) metaphysical; either national materialism or national spiritualism,
2) psychological (Renan); voluntarist, or
3) empirical (causal determinism as in Stalin/Lenin); defining criteria of territory, language, etc.

3) Yiddshe Arbeiter Bund

In multiculturalism the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is oftentimes associated with a territory or province within the context of a State. The initiative of Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire concluded with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred with the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other.

By origin the concept of national-cultural autonomy was formulated by the Yidisher Arbeter Bund of Eastern Europe which identified a national consciousness beyond the bounds of any of the States where it was found. The Bund’s conception was based both on a secular identity of Jewishness and a localized sense of integration with the country of residence, usually that being Poland. The national identity proclaimed was that of a Polish-Jewish nationality but without a territory of its own per se.

A civil society arising from the basis of social interaction rises in contradiction to the nation-state that harbours a superstructure around that base with the repressive apparatus and economic strictures necessary to maintain a certain social cohesion. The implosion of such social constraints develops under the dual dynamics of social tension and class revolt due to the apartheid-like conditions by which the proletariat is stratified into its various national communities. This duel oppression serves to differentiate the society into the various movements that seek out their self-determination for both social and economic causes.

4) Conclusion

The foundation of co-existence is to be sought in the constitutional assembly which brings together, in direct democracy, all social formations concerned to formulate and codify the means of social existence based upon their mutual actuality and not the temporal superstructure that represents one particular interest or set of particular interests.

Abstract brief

The State and National-Cultural Autonomy
By Abraham Weizfeld

For
The Association for the Study of Ethnicity and Nationalism

2008 ASEN Conference

“Nationalism, East and West:
Civic and Ethnic Conceptions of Nationhood”

April 15-16, 2008, at the London School of Economics

The dichotomy of civic and ethnic identity is contextualized by the State and social multiculturalism, respectively. Consequently the nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. The incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism” that is integral to the antinomy. At its origin the Hegelian concept of the Nation-State presented national identity as the State rather than in its social Form of multiculturalism. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Israel/Palestine.

In multiculturalism the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is oftentimes associated with a territory or province within the context of a State. The initiative of Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire concluded with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred with the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other. By origin the concept of national-cultural autonomy was formulated by the Yidisher Arbeter Bund of eastern Europe which identified a national consciousness beyond the bounds of any of the States where it was found.

While the contradiction of the nature of national-cultural autonomy with respect to the State leads us out of the context of the State, the alternative remains unresolved. In default of which the tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations. Ultimately the separation of ethnicities is recognized as an impossibility, or a war crime against human rights.

The foundation of co-existence is to be sought in the constitutional assembly which brings together, in direct democracy, all social formations concerned to formulate and codify the means of social existence based upon their mutual actuality and not the temporal superstructure that represents one particular interest or set of particular interests.

Based upon the doctoral Thesis
Nation, Society and The State:
the reconciliation of Palestinian and Jewish Nationhood, 2005.

The State and National-Cultural Autonomy

By Abraham Weizfeld

For
The Association for the Study of Ethnicity and Nationalism

2008 ASEN Conference

“Nationalism, East and West:
Civic and Ethnic Conceptions of Nationhood”

April 15-16, 2008, at the London School of Economics

Abstract

The dichotomy of civic and ethnic identity is contextualized by the State and social multiculturalism, respectively. Consequently the nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. The incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism” that is integral to the antinomy. At its origin the Hegelian concept of the Nation-State presented national identity as the State rather than in its social Form of multiculturalism. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Israel/Palestine.

In multiculturalism the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is oftentimes associated with a territory or province within the context of a State. The initiative of Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire concluded with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred with the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other. By origin the concept of national-cultural autonomy was formulated by the Yidisher Arbeter Bund of eastern Europe which identified a national consciousness beyond the bounds of any of the territories where it was found.

While the contradiction of the nature of national-cultural autonomy with respect to the State leads us out of the context of the State, the alternative remains unresolved. In default of which the tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations. Ultimately the separation of ethnicities is recognized as an impossibility, or a war crime against human rights.

The foundation of co-existence is to be sought in the constitutional assembly which brings together, in direct democracy, all social formations concerned to formulate and codify the means of social existence based upon their mutual actuality and not the temporal superstructure that represents one particular interest or set of particular interests.

Based upon the doctoral Thesis
Nation, Society and The State:
the reconciliation of Palestinian and Jewish Nationhood, 2005.

The primordial forms of religion are the means by which a nation or community formulates a code or doctrine to perpetuate itself in eternity by means of consciousness. This eternity is considered a divine attribute, when in fact it has the purpose of forming a national collectivity or enduring community. These forms of collectivity provide for those essential interests which cannot be achieved by other means. This striving for the eternity of identity cannot be achieved by a less coherent social formation or the individual entity itself. Identity is the focus of attention since such an historical memory contains the elements of human consciousness itself, in addition to the sense of self-defence necessary for its survival. The religious conception of the Nation considers ‘Le Moi’ as the image of the Nation that can accomplish that which it cannot itself, as in a Divine figure. The absolutist conception of the self in a religious framework creates the Monarchy with its ideology, among its adherents. The resulting monarchist conception of self-determination is Statism in its material elaboration. Such a national entity seeks to derive some exclusive privilege in competition with any other such social entity, and so there arises its need for a State, to define the privileges of a property.

While the Statist ideology conceives of survival as a competitive striving for scarce resources — as if it represents a private interest in property — the Nation has traditionally conceived of survival as simply a matter of life. The eternity of the Nation is concerned with sustaining life in its children, not in the power centres of the State. Power as a phenomenon seeks to justify its own existence for no other reason than by definition, a vicious tautology. The State is a concept created for the accumulation of power in a competitive methodology rather than in any creative praxis, that is, a corporate entity seeking to expand itself as if in a self-proclaimed principle of self-determination. This is reminiscent of the masculine cultural attribute in which survival means victory over animal food sources, or human competitors, as opposed to the feminine trait of food cultivation or conciliation. The Nation is more associated with the feminine cultural attributes. As in the HAUDENOSAUNEE Native Confederacy, it is the women who maintain the chief.

1.0 In Relation to Political Theory of Nationalism

The original distinction made between the intertwined ‘exclusive nationalism’ and ‘inclusive nationalism’, as in the treatment of nationalism by Hans Kohn, undergoes a transformation as significant as the differentiation between Nation and State. Thus, ‘exclusive nationalism’ becomes simply ‘nationalism’, that is, the nationalist ideology of the State, and ‘inclusive-pluralist nationalism’ (cosmopolitanism) becomes ‘national-identity’; as in the sense of a social formation. As such, the Hegelian Nation-State conception is negated by a federated Civil Society with multiple Nations, each with its particular civil society, all united in the Republic by its Civil Constitution.

In such a multi-national social environment there are indefinite numbers of identities ranging from the individual to one or more national-identities; whether or not they happen to be associated with an existing State. The concept of National-Identity tends to dissolve the effort made to unite the Nation with the State. Karl Renner referred to; ‘state and nation are antitheses of the same order as those of state and society’ (Gechtman 2005:8). Likewise, the attempts to fuse the State to Civil Society fail, in light of the ‘National-Identity’ concept — Renner’s ‘personality principle’. The independence of Civil Society is only guaranteed by its auto-sufficiency in operation with an economy that is community-oriented operating as a social-collective. The nature of the collective social economy is methodologically similar to its civil society, as determined by the nature of the federative pluralist social relations, rather than having a civil society suffocated by the dominance of the private sector or, by State monopolization of the economic institutions.

The need for the operative distinction between national-identity and nationalism is apparent from a critique of the political theories of nationalism. Shafer delimits nationalism to the modern era,
Nationalism, historically, is one of many group loyalties, a special and more or less unique form that first began to manifest itself rather late in human history, probably – though the question is debatable – during the late Middle Ages in western Europe and England. Not until the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries did it begin to assume something like this modern form and then again, chiefly, in western Europe and England (Shafer 1972:8).

even while recognizing that ‘Nations, however, may not have an autonomous or independent government or state’ (Shafer 1972:16), in effect dissociating nationalism from studies of the Nation.

Within the framework of the liberal idealisation of the individual seeking an egalitarian universalism of either bourgeois or Marxist inspiration, there is a lack of comprehension of what Gellner calls ‘romantic nationalism’ (Gellner 1995:2). The Modern notion of identity was presumed to have surpassed the “mere enculturation of the daily activities of a local group” (Gellner 1995:3). It has become evident more recently that this is not the case. Gellner explains this deficiency in liberal theory as an aspect of uneven development that leaves some localities in a relative disadvantage leading to the perpetuation of an idealized defence mechanism which manifests itself as ‘nationalism’, situated amongst what he chooses to call, ‘cultural pools’(Gellner. 1995:4). This approach coincides with that of Benedict Anderson who also refers explicitly to ‘imagined community’ (Gellner. 1995:4). The ‘primordialist’ position, as it is considered, nonetheless sustains its identity with the ‘nation’ in spite of its premature burial by liberalism.

The territorial association with ‘nationalism’ is proposed as an inherent propensity of national identity by way of the defined characteristics of a State. This Statist conception of the nation is derived from the presumption of national identity rooted in an organic rural element rather than in civil society. Gellner’s ‘populist nationalism’ is characteristically Gemeinschaft, inward looking and exclusivist, even though ‘national-identity’ succeeds in forming a collective consciousness that surpasses the atomized units of the State that is characteristic of the Gesellschaft, Gellner himself recognises:
The nationalist vision and the social reality which engenders it, cut across the Platonic/Kantian dichotomy. Nationalism borrows its imagery and verbiage from the organic option, but is based largely on the social reality of anonymous atomized society (Gellner 1995:2).

The dichotomy between Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft is parallel to the classic distinction made between ‘le moi’ et ‘le non-moi’ extrapolated into collective identities i.e. between the individual and the social context that one finds oneself in, one social context found within another, and so forth. The ideological hedge comes into play when the individual is identified solely with the self and its manifestation in the State, as if all the citizens shared in a monarchical power. The State effaces such identities in the campaign for homogenization, called democracy or, Majoritarianism. The Gemeinschaft is exemplary of the ‘self’, although it is also interpreted as ‘identity’. As such ‘le non-moi’, extrapolated into le autrie / les autries, may take on a collective sense as in Gesellschaft.

The coordination of these parallels is found in the necessary reciprocity of identity. In these terms the State is overruled as a substitute for personal and collective identity/ies. Gellner’s confondement of Society with the State in his references to community and society is presented as the dichotomy between the ‘organic’ and ‘citizenship’ criteria. The lack of distinction between the participants in a society and the citizenship of a State leads to a definition of the Nation that is a State-defined National status. Thus territory is considered a fundamental imperative to Nation; ‘Roots are indeed rural: the imaginary community invoked by the new ethos is territorial and has intimate links to the land.‘ (Gellner 1995:4). That ‘populist nationalism’ thus excludes of the Jewish People per se who are considered déraciné and so by consequence and according to such methodology, logically subject to ‘antisemitism’. On the other hand he nonetheless conceives of a Jewish Nation when, ‘Zionism created not merely a fine military instrument which saved Israel in 1948 … it also restored, with a vengeance, the imbalance in ‘roots’ ’ (Gellner 1995:5) by the creation of an ‘artificial peasant’ in the kibbutz. This fixation with the land and its State ignores the majority of the Jewish Nation, which abstains from adopting the identity provided by the ‘Land of Israel’ as the State. Such a view also requires one to ignore the urban concentration of the Israeli Jewish residents, 78% of whom still occupy only 14% of the land surface of the pre-1967 Zionist State, 60 years after the establishment of this ‘Nation-State’ . This political construction becomes the rationale in recognising the Nation simply by virtue of it being a State called The Land of Israel, ‘Eretz Israel’. On the other hand, the Palestinian fellaheen peasant roots do not appear in the methodology of the ‘roots’ of this ‘populist nationalism’. Gellner’s criteria for a Nation falls into a self-contradictory formality, incapable of recognizing a peasant-based National entity because it lacked a State, even though a peasant class is considered essential to a Nation according to Gellner.

As such, Gellner’s approach is absent a criterion by which one may discern the emergence of a ‘virulent’ nationalism, as he concludes, ‘all this does not mean that nationalism may not once again re-emerge in its virulent form. … It may do so. The question is open, and must obviously be our main concern.’(Gellner 1995:7). The concern with the re-emergence of a “virulent nationalism” is an expectation that is not misplaced even while its root cause is not taken into consideration. Gellner maintains that, ‘ … nationalism is not the awakening of nations to self-consciousness; it invents nations where they do not exist.’ (Periwal, ed. 1995:11) so asserting his Statist hypothesis, as if a nation does not have an existence prior to forming a State. Since the State is essential to the theory of nationalism, he is thus blinded to the effect of the State upon the Nation. This is why the root cause of virulence in nationalism is obscured as the State instills an ideology of nationalism fostering an exclusive Monist identity .

Although Benedict Anderson differs with Gellner over the lack of appreciation for the prior existence of the Nation, Anderson as well leaves the Nation as an imaginary entity which is created in the Form of the State. And so he makes reference to the “essential correctness of Gellner’s point” (Hall 1995:11).

Michael Mann, in his A Political Theory of Nationalism and its Excesses (1995), sets up the nut of the problem to be defined. On his way to the identity of the State and the Nation he forgives ‘state militarism’, in the name of the Nation, rather than the State, but only by the assumption of the dual identity made of the Nation-State.
But the clarity of focus on the nation as conterminous with the state cries out for a predominantly political explanation. Self-conscious nations emerged from the struggle for representative government, initially born of the pressures of state militarism. Whatever atrocities were later committed in the name of the nation, its emergence lay with those democratic ideals of this period that we most value today (Mann 1995:48) .

Nonetheless, this phenomenon is distinct from the process of national democratization and auto-determination.

The original class and social struggles in their particular national contexts, were and are tendencies in the process of democratization that has swept the continents and the centuries as illustrated by Michael Mann (1995:48) , now including gender and national identities (otherwise known as ethnic/cultural minorities). The consequence has been significant for the various struggles that have developed as a result of the combined character of the joint class and national dynamic. This combined nation-class is named an ‘Order’ in classical theory and is elaborated by Maxime Rodinson as a ‘People-class’. This aspect of permanent revolution arrives with the confluence of the various national formations in society, each of which seek the status of an equal person, and as such national identity, by consequence. The process itself continues in spite of the absence of a State to claim the Form of the emergent Nation.

The criterion for an emergent Nation is recognized as being dependent upon the proliferation of institutions of self-expression forming a civil society serving to distinguish a People as a Nation . A further analysis by John Keane based upon the Yugoslav crisis sums up the advances made in this respect;
The Badinter report ‘de-politicizes’ and de-territorializes’ national identity. It recaptures something of the eighteenth-century view, championed by thinkers like Burke and Herder, that nationality is best understood as a cultural entity; that is, as an identity belonging to civil society, not the state. It sees national identity as a civil entitlement of citizens, the squeezing or attempted abolition of which, even when ostensibly pursued by states in the name either of higher forms of human solidarity or of protecting the ‘core national identity’ (Isaiah Berlin), serves only to trigger off resentment, hatred and violence among national groupings (Keane 1995:201).

With the obligation to differentiate such social movements from the exercise of State-sponsored nationalism, Mann found it convenient to refer to ‘state-subverting nationalism’, a self-contradictory formulation, but appropriate. Mann also makes the association between the ‘state-subverting nationalism’ and the nature of civil society that is named federalism.
Since regionalists deeply opposed the former [Habsburg centralists], they increasingly sought to expand the latter, first into genuine federalism involving regional autonomies, then (when the empire would not concede this) into state-subverting nationalism (Mann. 1995:49).

This use of the term ‘state-subverting nationalism’ is the indication of a consciousness that is not essentially nationalist, in the Statist sense. This necessitates its own conceptual term which is associated with the Nation even though it is not tied to the State; this is national-identity. As Keane acknowledges, ‘The distinction between national identity and nationalism – overlooked by many commentaries on the subject, including Eric Hobsbawm’s Nations and Nationalism since 1780 – is fundamental in this context.’ (Keane.19:191). This distinction is related to his fundamental distinction that, ‘democracy requires the institutional division between a certain form of state and civil society’ (Keane.1995:187), a Civil Society in the sense of res publica.

The recognition and resolution of national-identity is to be found in federalism, although Mann and the theories of nationalism fail to resolve the co-existence of national-identity in the State, concluding pessimistically;

Mild nationalism – whether state-reinforcing or state-subverting – is democracy achieved, aggressive nationalism is democracy perverted. The solution is therefore, to achieve democracy – especially federal, inter-regional democracy. Unfortunately, this is easier said than done (Mann 1995:62).

While having drawn the distinction between State-driven nationalism and the consciousness of state-subverting nations, Mann does not apply the differentiation necessary between Nation and State to postulate a form of federalism that is other than a self-contradictory mirage of a civil society that is supposedly independent of the State. Democracy remains imprisoned in Liberal theory by its subordination to the State taken as the Form of the Nation.

Theories of federalism nonetheless make some advances in terms of the treatment of consociationalism and Max Weber follows such prescriptions for a ‘federation of nationalities under a supranational state’ (Periwal, ed. 1995:96) much along the lines that were later expressed by the humanist-Zionist tendency associated with Martin Buber, who proposed a ‘multi-national state, based upon parity among the various nationalities’ (Buber 1946:46). Such proposals have not been fulfilled and remained idealist conceptions only due to the failure to distinguish the Nation from the State and national-identity from nationalism. Keane recognizes the problem and makes reference to Karl Deutsch as symptomatic of this problematic impasse.

‘State’ and ‘’nation’ came to be used interchangeably … Such expressions reinforce the assumption traceable to the eighteenth century, that there is no other way of defining the word ‘nation’ than as a territorial aggregate whose various parts recognize the authority of the same state, an assumption captured in Karl Deutsch’s famous definition of a nation as ‘a people who have hold of a state’ (7) (Keane 1995:19).

The theorist Elie Kedourie recognizes this failure of federalism in the Statist context,

The national state claims to treat all citizens as equal members of the nation, but this fair-sounding principle only serves to disguise the tyranny of one group over another (Kedourie 1996:127).

This pessimism is only a consequence of the ideological exclusivity of Statism and its ideology of nationalism which Kedourie describes as follows,
In nationalist doctrine, language, race, culture, and sometimes even religion, constitute different aspects of the same primordial entity, the nation. The theory admits here on no great precision, and it is misplaced ingenuity to try and classify nationalisms according to the particular aspect which they choose to emphasize. What is beyond doubt is that the doctrine divides humanity into separate and distinct nations, claims that such nations must constitute sovereign states, and asserts that the members of a nation reach freedom and fulfilment by cultivating the peculiar identity of their own nation and by sinking their own persons in the greater whole of the nation (Kedourie 1996:73).

In reference to the Austrian Social Democrates’ (Otto Bauer and Karl Renner) proposal for national-cultural autonomy in the context of the Austro-Hungarian empire, Kedourie concludes;
… attempts to stem the tide of nationalist discontents are seldom successful, since nationalists consider that political and cultural matters are inseparable, and that no culture can live if it is not endowed with a sovereign state exclusively its own (Kedourie 1996:116-117) .

Here the reference to political and cultural matters is symptomatic of the problem in that cultural identity is not considered ‘political’ in and of itself. The artificial dichotomy made between culture and politics in the nationalist context is the difficulty. Culture is thus postulated as being political only in the context of the State.

In the analysis of Power by Karl Deutsch, social cohesion is based upon the means of communication rather than the means of production and although his theory is relatively abstract he has chosen to put aside the ‘subjective’ definitions of nation as superficial. In so far as his orientation to the forms of communication remains materialist , with its cultural and economic consequences, his theory remains dislocated or abstract since it does not situate culture in the organisms which transmit such consciousness, and that is found in Civil Society. National formations are consequently debased to, ‘oppressed, submerged, or otherwise disadvantaged groups … [such as] Negro fellow citizens’, when they are subject to a lack of Power. The preconception of the Nation as a ‘People’ self-conscious of its corporate identity based in a unity formed by the State, is tied to the formulations of Burke (Deutsch 1966:21).

The notion of society in Deutsch is only defined in economic terms (Deutsch 1966:29) while civil society is unmentioned and subjected to an extensive theory of social communication related to the economy again and only referred to as ‘The inner source of political power’ (Deutsch 1966:75), very much in the economic determinist tradition . Consequently, the nation is only considered as such according to Deutsch by virtue of the attribute of power which compels other such formations to recognize it as a sovereign nation. The defining characteristic of the nation according to Deutsch is simply power, in any other case he defines such formations as nationalities although they are otherwise indistinguishable from nations in general (Deutsch 1966:97,101,104). Such a criterion is simply a form of alienation by which the nation is considered from the externalized perspective alone which presents itself to the world at large by means of its self-governing economy thus becoming of interest to other such formations. As Deutsch puts it in his flippant manner, ‘The nation-state, it seems, is still the chief political instrument for getting things done’ (Deutsch 1966:2,4,75). The practice of using the term nationalities by Deutsch and others is an effort to overcome the actualities of national formations which are not befitted with its own State, thereby revealing the contradiction of the Nation-State concept as in John Kautsky’s, ‘…nationalism, the identification of state and nationality’ (Kautsky 1976:32). The utility of the term nationality is only appropriate for those nations which are situated in a number of different States, such as the Jewish, Palestinian, Kurdish, Berber, Gitan/Roma, Basque or Kashmiri case or, on behalf of a nation associated with a State but living also in a number of other States, such as the well known hyphenated Canadians or other such immigrant communities or national minorities; British-Canadians, French-Canadians, Irish-Americans, German-Americans, African-Americans, Jewish-Americans, or Israeli-Americans (Kly 1986:26).

The ‘National Principle’ substitutes State for Nation as if to contradict Kedourie’s awareness of the difference between perception and objective reality which explains how the perceived sense of a sovereign State is only an apparent manifestation of the Nation.

… the sensations which the categories of our mind transform into objective experience we only know in space and time. Now space and time, Kant argued, are not properties of things; they are rather something contributed by the perceiving self to the sensations impinging on it (Kedourie 1996:33).

In theories of nationalism the Nation is perceived as a State and so assume the necessity of the latter, although Kedourie himself reveals in various instances how the Nation is historically independent of the State. His failing to maintain the differentiation of Nation and State into their derivatives, of national-identity and nationalism, leads to the collapse of this analysis and nationalist theories in general, as he admits;

The invention [nationalism] has prevailed, and the best that can be said for it is that it is an attempt to establish once and for all the reign of justice in a corrupt world, and to repair, for ever, the injuries of time. But this best is bad enough, since to repair such injuries other injuries must in turn be inflicted, and no balance is ever struck in the grisly account of cruelty and violence. … It is a question which, in the nature of the case, admits of no final and conclusive answer (Kedourie 1996:139).

This is not to say that all theories of the Nation have been tainted with Statism. One may seek theoretical treatments of the Nation that do not limit themselves to State forms of appearance. The problem is rooted in the Eurocentric definition of State which is found in the Treaty of Westphalia Article VI, ‘… States (therein comprehending the Nobility, which depend immediately on the Empire) …’ (1648). The economism at the core of the problematic is exposed by Bauer when the ‘non-historic Nation’ was taken into consideration in spite of the attributes of a lack of economic development and partially formed class structure, together with no defined territory. As such the ideal conceived by Bauer, as inspired by the Bundist Vladimir Medem, was for the recognition of such nationalities as a means to avert their eventual separation into a State of their own. Medem’s conception of such autonomy was more so based on the cultural attributes of national identity rather than an economic criterion. Such a cultural criterion in terms of language allowed for the identity of the eastern European Jewish Nation in spite of a lack of a common territory. The lack of recognition for such a national-cultural autonomy in their respective contexts was a consequence of the myopia of the State which remained centred in the dominant nation by means of the national bourgeois hegemony in the State. Subsequently such formations fragmented into various States as the national bourgeoisie of the nationalities became sufficiently endowed to proclaim its economic independence as a State.

The colleague of Martin Buber’s, the Jewish-German political philosopher Gustav Landauer, went beyond the confines of the State to declare that,

The state, with its police and all its laws and its contrivances for property rights, exists for the people as a miserable replacement for Geist [Nation] and for organisations with specific purposes; and now the people are supposed to exist for the sake of the state, which pretends to be some sort of ideal structure and a purpose in itself, to be Geist. … Earlier there were corporate groups, clans, gilds, fraternities, communities, and they all interrelated to form society. Today there is coercion, the letter of the law, the state (Maurer 1971:93).

As in Kedourie, Michael Mann chooses to differentiate between Nation and State without drawing the corollary of the distinction between national-identity and nationalism. By identifying the State with the self-realization of the Nation as an independent self-sufficient and sustainable entity, there is a general lack of correspondence of national entities and a given State since organic diversity cannot correspond to the formal limitations of the State. As a result, the theories of nationalism treat national conflict as inevitable.

The danger rests that having distinguished between Nation and State, the ‘National Doctrine’, in defining the State as an essential attribute giving precedence to the existence of the State rather than the Nation turns against itself in principle. The rationalization of the Hegelian State continues in the name of the Nation but not as the Nation, only as ‘nationalism’.

Landauer’s rejection of the State allows him to have remained aloof from the Zionist movement, unlike Buber. He remarks, ‘Strong emphasis on one’s own nationality, even when it does not lead to chauvinism, is weakness ’ (Maurer 1971:81). His subsequent rejection of a Zionist State was indicative of such analysis. The prospect he projects of a Gesellschaft von Gesellschaften (a society of societies) is reminiscent of the Proudhon formulation in his Federal Principle; ‘a federation of federations’.

One is thus obligated to move outside the parameters and paradigms of the political theory of nationalism if there is to be a resolution of the incompatibilities presented by the Statist model. Trevor Purvis also concludes that, ‘as a hegemonic project, the unity of the people-nation constituted by the modern state has always been open to contestation. In turn this has implied an open character to the nation, one that belies its mythological closure in the discourses of nationalism’ (Purvis 1996:51).

While the works on nationalism are rich in overview and opinion, the approach that is explored in this work seeks to meet the needs of current conflict resolution and in particular the Palestinian-Zionist knot. It is with such a perspective in mind that one may express the desire for the means by which such a conflict may be resolved, by meeting the essential needs of each nation involved, leaving aside the categorical imperatives of the State. It is precisely in this respect that the character and attributes of national-cultural autonomy as elaborated by Otto Bauer and Karl Renner will serve the development of those societies that have need of an alternate constitutional framework to overcome the inherent stasis of the State in conflict with its own Society. As in the dissociation of theocracy from the State, the de-linking of the Nation and territory allows national-cultural autonomy to form the basis of Civil Society.

2.0 Collective Consciousness

The ‘Common Will’ of Hegel and the ‘General Will’ of Rousseau are the two conceptions which dominate the Modern Era. The Common Will pertains to the Nation while the General Will refers to the citizenry of a State, so leading to their possible contradiction. That is, a certain precise differentiation must be made between the Hegelian concept of the Common Will and the Rousseauian General Will, as the former is concerned with national-identity itself, and the latter is concerned with the Civil Society as formed by the citizenry — without reference to nationality. In effect the two are opposed to one another in their nature rather than being similar, as may be implied. This national conception and the individualist perspective share an exclusive tendency though towards one focus, themselves. While Rousseau presents the notion of the State as being upheld for a pluralist alternative to the uniformity introduced by the model of the Nation, it has fallen into the homogenization induced by the dominant/majoritarian nationality. The proposition for an alternative to this impasse is based upon both these conceptions being fused in a pluralist civil society thus allowing for national-cultural autonomy and other collective identities, in federation. This dynamic method of operation would be interactive between national identities in a pluralist setting with multiple foci. Such is the natural equilibrium found in the ellipse of the animal’s egg, or the planet’s orbit, and so also acts Civil Society which remains in perpetual change even while the traditional is preserved.

The consideration given to the territory as a fundamental criterion often leads to the confusion between its aspects. It may be stated that territory is one means by which a Nation forms its societal environment, even though society itself is not subordinate to territory. The resulting inversion between the social context and territory is the result, as in Gellner. Actually it is rather the economy that is directly linked to a given territorial site in most cases, especially in agricultural societies. The distinction between Nation and territory is based in the choice of methodology; either the materialism of economic determinism or a multi-faceted problematic. The economism integral to Statism merely recognizes those Nations which replicate a similar economic and structural Content as tautology. It is necessary to bring the concept of Nation out of the hierarchical schemas in order to reveal its real nature. That distinction made in respect to territory, provides the basis for the conception of the Nation as a People rather than a materialist fetish. The primordial and enduring conception of the Nation is based in the collective self-identity of the People who form a distinct culture, having a particular historical experience, and origin, who wish to form a civil society to maintain such an historical acquisition in perpetuity.

This phenomenon is described by Rudolf Rocker as;
The national-suppression policy of the great states before the War developed in the suppressed nationalities an extreme nationalism which finds expression today in the according by the new-made states of the same treatment to their national minorities which, as national minorities, they themselves once received — a phenomenon showing all too clearly that little states following the footsteps of great ones and imitate their practices (Rocker 1978:349).

The quandary that presents itself is that the States that are presented with the fait accompli of minority nationalities are obliged to recognize identities that contradict its own rationale for existence as a centralized superstructure provoking territorially-based nationalities to seek their own State apparatus in a never-ending spiral of ever smaller Statelets, each seeking to preserve its own sovereignty with a State of its own. The current proposition for a ‘Two-State Solution’ is indicative of this methodology which seeks to give rise to two or three Palestinians Statelets, or Bantustans, in effect.

As in any methodological impasse, the illusory antinomies of national conflict are subsumed by a breakthrough based in a fundamental realignment of conceptual identities. In such a process the Modern perspective is inverted reciprocally to reverse the direction of the hierarchical emission of authority, to annul the monopoly of power. A social entity is examined from within, in the context of the many parallel phenomena externally, rather than from an external ethnocentric and therefore alienated point of view. This extraneous void, presumably absent of any other national context, is actually a competing national perspective, a self-perpetuating agency seeking to develop its singular economic base to better nourish itself as a parasite on its subjects as sacrifices, known as either slaves, citizens or soldiers. This is the game of hegemony that is played by aggressive State entities, whether Empires or, Nation-States. Karl Deutsch puts it well saying, ‘It leads to the loss of self-determination, nationalism at the end of its tether becomes a force for the destruction of the nation.’ (Deutsch 1966:184)

While the national concept parallels class consciousness in grandeur and profundity, class consciousness is in any case itself posited for dissolution according to the classical theorist in the matter, so leaving national consciousness as the determinant factor in social development. The consequence of this conclusion is to reverse the roles of Form and Content from Hegel’s supposition, making the Nation the Form rather than being Content in the State. The Nation emerges out of the envelope of the State so enabling Civil Society.

The interfacing with more extensive and varied social groupings constitutes a developmental process both internally and externally for the national entity. Naturally one manner of ameliorating the social consciousness would be through the elaboration of reciprocal national consciousness in the inter/intra-national/s context. The absence of an intermediary State superstructure allows for a Reciprocal Principle whereby no one identity takes precedence over the other by definition. The direction observed being taken during historical development is towards ever larger networks in a harmonious interaction, expanding without limit, boundless, and permanent — a continuous surpassing of limitations in federated reciprocity.

-end-

Abraham Y. Weizfeld completed the doctoral dissertation Nation, Society and The State: the reconciliation of Palestinian and Jewish Nationhood at l’Université du Québec à Montréal, having published the documentary study Sabra-Shatila (1984) and the anthology The End of Zionism: and the liberation of the Jewish People (1989). He is currently working on a second edition of the essay The Abrahamic Tradition.

—-

Endnotes

THE LIBYAN EXPERIENCE 2005

2013/11/30

From: Abraham-eibie Weizfeld
Sent: 27 septembre, 2005 09:01

THE LIBYAN EXPERIENCE
by Abraham Weizfeld Ph.D. cand. l’Universite du Quebec a Montreal
SaaLaHa@fokus.name
September 27th, 2005

The unknown genocide of the twentieth century is no longer the Armenian experience at the hands of the Turkish State, it is the Libyan fate under Italy’s occupation. Beginning in 1911 and culminating in the fascist regime of 1922 the occupation of this North African country continued until 1945. During this occupation the Libyan Arab population together with the indigenous Berber and Bedouin People’s were subjected to a genocidal campaign resulting in the loss of one million Libyans, half its population, much like the Armenians.
The Libyan resistance at the time is commemorated in the figure of Omar Maktar after whom the main street in Tripoli is now named, in addition to his image on the 10 dinar bill.
Such history is standard fare for Libya since it is a favourite site for colonization, extending back in history to the Roman Empire’s reign under which the Emperor Agustus Severus built the city of Leptis Magna dated at 234 C.E., with is columned streets, baths, public toilets, and forum still in the process of being unearthed and restored. Prior to Rome, Sparta also planted itself in the sandy soil of the Mediterranean African coast here even though such ruins have not yet been touched. Before the Greek influence, the ancient civilization of the Garamantinas flourished based upon the primordial humanoid appearance as far back as the Paleolithic period two and a half million years ago.
Known as Tripolitania and Punis during the Roman and Greek empire times, its history has culminated now in the rather elaborate name of The Great Socialist People’s Libyan Arab Jamahiriya (GSPLAJ). As a Mediterranean neighbour this society has absorbed the traditions of many political cultures to formulate its own expression of social thought called a Jamahiriya, or egalitarian Civil Society.
This method of thought is described in “The Green Book” presented by Muammar Kadhafi and while similar to the famous little “Red Book” of Mao Tse-tung it is rather a methodological work and not based on a particular political ideology and party platform. Actually, it disputes the need for ideology and political parties and conceives of a society based upon direct democracy organized on the basis of People’s Assemblies of which there are 453 in a politically active population of 1,400,000.
Kadhafi himself is considered the principal revolutionary guide and teacher to the “Jamahiriya” since the September 1st political revolution in 1969 which peacefully overthrew the king installed in 1953. While Kadhafi held the title of President, he resigned the post in 1973 with the abolition of the head of State in a cultural revolution culminating in the Proclamation of People’s Authority in 1977. The “Green Book” itself came out in 1980 followed by the “Great Green Charter of Human Rights of the Jamahiriyan Era” in 1988 which forms a constitutional document based in social consent and not a State superstructure. This Charter proposes to, “reject violence as a means intended to dictate ideas and opinion. They adopt the democratic dialogue as the one and only method of debate, … the members of Jamahiriyan society are free to form associations, trade unions and leagues in order to defend their professional interests.” Social law is based in the Islamic Sha’ria code’s political culture although it is judged by a people’s committee elected in assembly and not a religious theocracy led by Immam clerics. “Religion is personal to each one … Jamahiriyan society proscribes the monopoly of religion.” Together with economic rights and national self-determination, the Charter goes well beyond the constitutional rights of occidental constitutions.
Libya has had a minimal record in terms of political prisoners, who are associated with violence and the Islamic Alliance Movement. According to Amnesty International, Libya is engaged in the liberation of such cases in spite of various attempts at assassination and the U.S.A.’s bombardment of the Kadhafi home in 1986. The most recent Amnesty report of September 26th refers to “The recent release by Libyan authorities of five long-term prisoners of conscience” as “an encouraging step”. The Kadhafi Foundation spokesperson Saif al Islam has indicated that the Foundation’s opinion about the prisoners who had endorsed armed action and violence is that since they could no longer constitute any threat to society, many of them could be reinstated. Nowadays, the external opposition to the Libyan Jamahiriya has melted away and mutual diplomatic recognition has been established with first Canada and then the U.S.A. It is well known that Libya has halted any development of nuclear arms as was previously specified in the “Green Charter” of 1988 where, “The members of Jamahiriyan society call for the suppression of nuclear, bacteriological and chemical weapons …”. In addition, it has become known now that evidence used in the conviction of a Libyan security agent Abdelbaset Ali Al-Megrahi in the Lockerbie airline tragedy was fabricated, according to the local Scottish police chief (see News.Scotsman.com article by Marcello Mega). In spite of the case of a Libyan civilian airliner shot down in 1973 over the Sinai Peninsula area by Israel military aircraft, Libya has been burdened by a common perception in the North American public mind as a sort of rogue state and was even listed as a country susceptible to attack from the U.S.A., as is Iraq presently. Currently though the long-standing embargo on Libya has been lifted.
Since the time of that cold war, the Libyan “Jamahiiyan Era” fostered the formation of the African Union in 1999, based in the former OAU, Organization of African Unity of post-colonial days.
The current condition in Libya is marked by continued transformation in economic terms with agricultural self-sustainability nurtured by the sub-Saharan waters brought to the coastal population by the unprecedented human-made river of a water pipeline. Economic enterprises are being socialized by being sold to their former workers who are becoming partners. As well, external private corporations from Canada, many European countries, Bangladesh, the U.S.A., Britain, and Dubai are bidding for importation and development contracts. This burst of economic activity follows from the end of the complete embargo enforced against Libya until recent years.
Both the current oil wealth and the past embargo are the consequence of Libya’s role in securing the rise of the crude oil price from the 1960’s level of around $12 a barrel. This non-renewable resource began at 25 cents a barrel in colonial days and has now reached $65 USD and is projected to reach $150 a barrel in the coming years based upon its actual value. Although this price rise initiated by Libya introduces a strain to the markets whose wealth has previously been based on cheap resources, this re-evaluation of resource values from the former “Third World” will make the development of renewable resources and technology economically feasible.
As has been proposed previously, the future is now and so many aspects of future developments are to be found in this land in which the long past is also the present.

National-Cultural Autonomy and The State (SSS)

2013/11/30

Session: The State and Civil Society
Chair: Abraham Weizfeld

For
Society for Socialist Studies
J.2 The State and Civil Society 10:45-12:15 Mackenzie 3174
Congress of the Humanities and the Social Sciences, Canada
Ottawa 2009

Abstract Session

The Nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. While the incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism”, national identity per se is associated with Civil Society. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Palestine/Israel or the impasse of Québécois/se national-identity, in the context of the Dominion of Canada.

The tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations.

National-Cultural Autonomy and The State
By Abraham Weizfeld
Independent Scholar
Montréal, QC, Canada
saalaha@fokus.name

1) Introduction

The dominion of the Nation-State has dominated The Modern Age with its culmination during the 20th Century of 125 million lost lives during those various wars, including even the mass annihilation by nuclear bomb, not to speak of the industrialized genocide by Nazism .

The fixed idea of the Nation-State continues the monarchist conceptualization that had begun with the deification of the head of State-Empire. The emancipation of the Nations Reformation was only brought about within the confines of the European State-Monarchy by means of the moral imperative of a national religious Authority; this provided the common consciousness needed for each social entity to coalesce as the Nation-State.

Considering the massive rejection of the Millet status as practised in the Ottoman Islamic Ummah, the status of a minority national identity is considered obsolete for the Jewish Arabs now Israeli citizens, as well as the Israel Palestinian communities and the Palestinian refugees.

There is the necessity for a strategic programme that surpasses each of the preceding constitutional arrangements that have been imposed by one form of state or another. The formulations for a bi-national State are suspect in that such a conception was also behind the verbiage of the South African Apartheid regime with advocated a ‘Separate but equal’ conception with was moreso a merit system which awarded equality by the definition provided by one party alone. Such a definition of rights was subject to the ideological rationale behind the State in the first place. Any State would have its ideological rationale. To remove the discussion from that State superstructure one has to consider constitutional formats such as a Confederation or Federation in the context of Civil Society and not the State, if it were to be reciprocal and operate on the basis of consensual understanding.

Such a conception was attempted by Otto Bauer in the context of the 1907 Austro-Hungarian Empire prior to the European World War I. While limited in its appreciation of social identity as a nation and to the significance of national oppression, Bauer projected the integration of society by the mutual recognition of national-cultural identity.

The conception of National-Cultural Autonomy is originally found in the Jewish Workers’ Bund and its history beginning in 1897, together with the Wimberg Austrian Social-Democratic Party congress which provided for internal national-cultural autonomy . Both sources are of interest in terms of the social infrastructure that is sought by each of the national identities that conceives of itself as such.

2) Otto Bauer and Austrian Social-Democracy

The proposition by Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire was concerned with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred in the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances, national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other. The lack of recognition of the various national minorities was a fundamental flaw in the perpetuation of the State. As such, the nationalities question was given a priority in spite of the centralizing dynamic of the State apparatus. The practice of majoritarianism was in itself central to the monolithic State operation and yet inimical to it survival.

Each nation would believe its own minorities to be disadvantaged and would see itself as able to combat the oppression of its own minorities by taking revenge on the minorities of other nations within its region. Thus, national self-determination on the basis of the territorial principle would simple provoke renewed national struggles.
For this reason alone, the territorial principle cannot satisfy the demands of the working class.

The need to overcome the majority criterion rooted in the dominant national culture in many cases was proposed to be overcome by the constitutional guarantee for collective representation of “sovereign corporations”. Such social formations exist in and of themselves without the concurrent definition of any majority and is intended to overcome the paradigm of majorities and minorities.

The topology of society became a dynamic soup of varying social currents and cultures all intertwined into a given geography but without a specific territory of its own. Such cosmopolitanism on a grand scale was the means by which loyalty to the State was to be achieved when the State became the guarantor of the national cultural autonomy that was held dearest by each particular culture.

In its pure form, the aim of the personality principle is to constitute the nation not as a territorial corporation, but as an association of persons.

The precedent provided by the Islamic Ummah of the Turkish Empire gave rise to the Millet system of national autonomy extended to the various social entities. The mosaic of autonomous cultures was an internally stable form of governance. The Dimuni status of such minorities was recognized, protected and taxed, for the effort (as if such status was provisional and secondary).

The democratic federation of national communities incubated by Otto Bauer challenged the notion of sovereignty in a unitary and indivisible construct replicated internationally by the principle of the self-determination of nations which require their nation-state with such national-states only recognizing other such nation-states. At the same time Bauer sought the perpetuation of the bourgeois Austro-Hungarian Empire. The limitations of the liberal democracies is demonstrated by the failure of Bauer to implement his programme in the Austrian context. The incompatibility of the European Nation-State with the relief offered by national-cultural autonomy, is a consequence of the hegemony of the dominant nation. The secondary nature of national-cultural autonomy as in the Millet system offered a suspect remedy to a bourgeois national class compact. The rejection of a federated autonomy is the prelude to the collapse of that nation-state. Either conception of society (Nation-State/Dimini) is, in consequence, the failure of a class dominated state since the dynamic of a state superstructure is to build itself on the social unit that most closely resembles itself. The monopolisation of the State power is dependent upon the hegemony of the dominant strata of the population, that being either the national bourgeoisie or the national proletariat. The viability of the project is put into doubt equally by the fact that not all social formations are represented, neither the minority nationalities or the subordinate gender strata within each of the nations involved, as well.

The effort to reconcile the various nations coexisting within the same political superstructure is a matter of accommodating the minority or non-dominant nationalities by means of a sort of autonomy. While it has been found that the autonomy granted the subordinated social formations such as the Québécois or the Palestinians is insufficient when limited to a provincial or a non-sovereign Authority, it is also the case that the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is itself incompatible with the nature of the sponsoring state in the first place.

By consequence, the various national liberation struggles of the 20th Century have sought to fit within the paradigm of what has become defined as a Nation. The formation of a nation-state is oftentimes confronted by the presence of further nationalities which contest the hegemony of that particular nation asserting its particular sovereignty. The exercise of self-determination in such circumstances becomes ethnic cleansing with the goal of building a predominant national charter to the social composition. This is in itself the replication of the original problem for which the nation has sought to escape by building its own nation-state. The attempts to induce a social assimilation by economic stimulation has failed on numerous occasions demonstrating that economic determinism or economic liberalism does not make a worker without a national-cultural identity.

The aspiration to national conquest within the multinational state is therefore based on good reasons as long as the nations conduct their struggle in terms of the pursuit of state power. The situation alters completely as soon as the atomist-centralist is replaced by the organic regulation of national relations. Here the state has nothing to offer the nations as totalities, and the power struggle of the nations therefore no longer has any point. The nation is legally assured the power it requires; it no longer struggles to obtain it. In this case, the nation therefore no longer needs to pursue national conquest.

While the contradiction of the nature of national-cultural autonomy with respect to the State leads us out of the context of the State, the alternative remains unresolved. In default of which, the tendency of the 20th Century had been to seek ever more numerous numbers of States which separate the various ethnic identities on a territorial basis with the accompanying series of ethnic cleansing operations. Ultimately, the separation of ethnicities is recognized as an impossibility, or a war crime against human rights.

The introduction of the concept of national-cultural autonomy then posits the nullification of the nation-state itself, as an expression of sovereignty. The intensity of this contradiction tends to increase with the continuing waves of human migration which have never abated since the emergence of the human species from east-central Africa beginning some 200,000 years ago.

While Bauer limited national-cultural autonomy to national minorities — in effect the second of two or more nations cohabiting — it is in its reciprocal application that the feasibility of a no-state strategy is conceived. The criterion of a majority is abandoned as being superficial, arbitrary and an abrogation of minority rights. Considering that all members of society are in a minority of one sort or another, this aspect addresses the fundamental nature of democratic theory.

Nimni’s introduction to Bauer provides the synopsis of the irreducibility of the forms of the social by arguing “that the process of common reciprocal interaction lived in a permanent reciprocal relations generates a national community and expresses itself in an intersubjective bond that shapes each ‘individual National identity’ ”. This social morphology (sozial Formenlehre) is linked to the will (Wille) expressed by Neitzsche in the sense that “will is the societalized expression of human existence … ‘national apperception’ “ often expressed as national character or the collective will (as in Gramsci) and the ‘community of fate’ (Schicksalsgemeinschaft) (in Nietzsche) . Kant’s Third Analogy of Experience, the principle of community that “All substances so far as they coexist, stand in thoroughgoing community, that is, in mutual interaction.”

The dichotomy of civic and ethnic identity is contextualized by the State and social multinationalism, respectively. Consequently, the nationalism associated with the State is counterpoised to the national identity associated with ethnicity, in the social context. The incorporation of ethnic national identity with the State gives rise to the “exclusive nationalism”. At its origin, the Hegelian concept of the Nation-State presented national identity as the State rather than in its social Form of multinationalism. The evident contradiction of the two concepts of national-identity and The State is found in the mutual demands for self-determination for a common territory, as is the case in Israel/Palestine.

The three schools of national theory thus are defined as:
1) metaphysical; either national materialism or national spiritualism,
2) psychological (Renan); voluntarist, or
3) empirical (causal determinism as in Stalin/Lenin); defining criteria of territory, language, etc.

3) Yiddshe Arbeiter Bund

In multinationalism the proposition for national-cultural autonomy is oftentimes associated with a territory or province within the context of a State. The initiative of Otto Bauer for national-cultural autonomy within the Austro-Hungarian Empire concluded with its failure to reconcile national-identity with the State, as occurred with the U.S.S.R. as well. In these instances national-identity was associated with territorial units as if the one substituted for the other.

By origin the concept of national-cultural autonomy was formulated by the Yidisher Arbeter Bund of eastern Europe which identified a national consciousness beyond the bounds of any of the States where it was found. The Bund’s conception was based both on a secular identity of Jewishness and a localized sense of integration with the country of residence, usually that being Poland. The national identity proclaimed was that of a Polish-Jewish nationality but without a territory of its own per se.

A civil society arising from the basis of social interaction arises in contradiction to the nation-state that harbours a superstructure around that base with the repressive apparatus and economic strictures necessary to maintain a certain social cohesion. The implosion of such social constraints develops under the dual dynamics of social tension and class revolt due to the apartheid-like conditions by which the proletariat is stratified into its various national communities. This duel oppression serves to differentiate the society into the various movements that seek out their self-determination for both social and economic causes.

4) Conclusion

The foundation of co-existence is to be sought in the constitutional assembly which brings together, in direct democracy, all social formations concerned to formulate and codify the means of social existence based upon their mutual actuality and not the temporal superstructure that represents one particular interest or set of particular interests.

The Bases of Nation, Society and State: the crisis of Canada

2013/11/30

The Bases of Nation, Society and State:  the crisis of Canada

 

by  Abraham Weizfeld

saalaha@fokus.name

(Science Politique)  l’Université du Québec à Montréal

 

Nationalism and Constitutional Crisis in Canada.

    Wednesday 5 June / mercredi 5 juin, 13:45-15:15, NR-400

Coordinator & chair: Lorne A. Brown (Political Science, Regina)

Society for Socialist Studies

Learneds, Brock University

~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~

Abstract

 

With the Canadian State in contradiction to the Kébékoize Nation,   the  General Will  (citizenry) opposes the  Common Will   (Nation).  Self-Determination fails as a solution because of,  the inevitability of an opposing self-determination,  and,  the question of who determines national identity.  The constitutional feasibility of sovereignty-association (national-cultural autonomy) is consequently dependent upon the construction of a pluralist society  (civil society)  replacing the State.  If this process takes longer amongst anglophone Canadians it would result in the separation of Québec (Kébèk).  However,  each of these social dynamics nurture the other,  as has been the experience in the past. 

~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~

Table  of  Contents

1……… The  Civic  Conception  of  Nation……………………………………………………………………….. 5

2……… The  Ethnic  Conception  of  Nation……………………………………………………………………… 8

3……… The  Evolution  of  the  Civic  and  Organic  Concepts………………………………………… 12

4……… National Minorities in the Modern Conceptions………………………………………………….. 14

5……… The   Liberal   Democratic   State……………………………………………………………………….. 15

6……… The   Federal   Principle…………………………………………………………………………………….. 17

7……… The  Iroquois  Confederation…………………………………………………………………………….. 18

8……… The Crisis of Canada…………………………………………………………………………………………. 22

            We know nationalism to be the conscious identity with a particular nation.  This then indicates the presence of  a nation.   This national identity,  is also defined as the collective consciousness  of a People,  with its culture, history, religion, language(s), or any other particularities perpetuated by such a People.  In this sense a nation is defined by a People,  since it is the people who conceive of the nation.

            By investigating the nature of nationalism we do not presume to balance the various elements that will  be laid out in order to provide an overall resultant of the worth of nationalism according to a moral or ideological standard.  We need to know what goes into making the consciousness of nationalism to determine its role among the political forces of social life.

            In this analysis there is no uniform nature of nationalism.  This phenomenon presents contradictory influences in different situations.  It also manifests contradictory characteristics simultaneously.  By the methodology applied in the implementation of the nationalist consciousness the contradictions may arise. It is no wonder then that the phenomenon of nationalism is described in such wildly divergent if not contradictory terms by different observers.  Therefore,  the treatment of nationalism that follows,  allows for contradictory tendencies and seeks to examine the opposing facets in and of themselves.  As a result,  we may then detect the consequences of the differing tendencies that are in effect.  The internally counterpoised characteristics of nationalism themselves define the nation in contradictory terms.  In order to examine the definitions of the nation we are obliged to look at the underlying consciousness that makes such criteria appear to be real.

             The matter of territory is confused between two aspects that appear to be the same;  the nation as the territory,  and the territory as nation!  This is the typical quandary that strikes the opening of the discussion of the nation.  These two aspects,  however,  are not the same when the nation does not entirely live in the same territory,  as amongst the Kébékois(ze) in Canada.

            In the relation between territory and nation evidently one is not necessarily identical to the other.  While a territory can be the common property of a nation,  it is not necessarily true that the territory defines the nation,  or that the nation shall define the territory.  If this were the case then this notion would become an exclusive defining aspect of such a conception of the nation .  By means of the citizenship granted by such a territorial administration, the hierarchical priority assumes that only the subjects of a State have a legal nationality . 

            The Dominion of Canada operates on the basis that there exists one legal national entity,  that being Canadian.  In a similar manner the territorially defined nation of the province of Québec exists in the context of State policy,  whereas the Québécoise (Kébékoiz)  nationality lives not only in that province but in various other provinces of Canada,  and certain States of the northeast U.S.A.  (2,835,398;  1990  US Census).  In addition there exist affiliated francophone nationalities with the Québécoise,  such as the Acadienne of New Brunswick and Louisiana,  the Métisse of Manitoba,  and various francophone indigenous peoples nationalities in the province of Québec itself.  Consequently,  a nation is grander than the particular members residing in the State administered territory which makes representation in the name of the nation. 

            The exclusive identity of a nation and a territory furthermore serves to define such a  territory as existing only for that nation and none other.  This construction of an empire as a country-state has its consequences in the differing modern examples of the Dominion of Canada,  among others  (settler-colonial states);  where the subjugated nation is maintained as a reserve class / order of workers.  The same tendency is also perpetuated among the workers in the economically dependent Canada in relation to the United States economy.  The subordinate position of the indigenous First Peoples of Québec and North America in the hierarchical order of nations results in the waste of their land’s natural resources without even the opportunity of a compensating position as wage workers.

            The aspirations of a national culture for self-sufficiency may be translated into becoming a discriminatory society if this self-sufficiency is conceived of as a thing in itself.  By such means the national culture is equated with the society as if there were no other nations that exist in the society.  That would be the conception of a State and the associated ideology of homogeneity.  Those nationalities that live under such a State without those collective social rights that are granted to regular members of the society,  are disfavoured because they are not of the same nationality who have established the State.  This State has the function of guarding the priority of a founding nation in the chosen territory,  by all necessary means.

            The State’s assimilation of national minorities can be observed in the context of the British Empire.  More recent reflections by similar means in modern times have perpetuated socio-economic discrimination derived from the hierarchical perspective.  Currently such nations as this have become the rural or urban toiling classes.  Resulting from the differences in origin between nations,  a people such as the African Americans,  or New Africans,  were formed from the lower classes in that manner.  In respect to Canada one can see the monarchist coat of arms with the symbol of the Province of Québec, the unicorn,  chained at the neck to a crown in place like a horse’s work-collar.  All this is printed on the front of the Canadian money bill,  like a trophy.

            With respect to the Kébékois(ze) People,  Katherine O’Sullivan See has noted that; 

The Durham Report,  which resulted from this investigation,  analyzed the situation in Canada as derivative from the fact of  ‘two nations warring in the bosom of a single state’.  Durham claimed that the solution to this war was simple:  the assimilation of the French was a prerequisite to Canada’s survival and to the economic survival of the group.  He wrote to the King: 

If they attempt to better their condition by extending themselves over the neighboring country,  they will get more and more mingled with the English population.  If they prefer remaining stationary,  the greater part of them must be labourers in the employ of the English capitalists.  In either case,  it would appear that in some measure,  the vast majority of French Canadians are doomed to occupy an inferior position and to be dependent upon the English for employment’  (Rioux 1971: 51)  [1]  

1.         The  Civic  Conception  of  Nation

            Faced with the problem of a divided society one is obliged to consider its modern underpinnings  in the references often given as justifications for the social projects that have been undertaken.

            The  moi  commune  of Rousseau acts as the incorporation of the general will into the body politic.  This is considered to be the formation of the city-state and not a nation[2],  although it is disputed insofar as the  general will   is regarded as being more than the sum of a collection of individuals.  Rousseau’s editor G.D.H. Cole presents the misconception;

The term  ‘general’  will  means,  in Rousseau,  not so much  ‘ will held by several persons ‘,  as will having a general  (universal)  object.  This is often misunderstood;  but the mistake matters the less,  because the General Will must,  in fact,  be both.  [3]

Rousseau’s conception is nonetheless definitively interested in making a differentiation between the two;

There is often a great deal of difference between the  will of all  and the  general will;  the latter considers only the common interest,  while the former takes private interest into account,  and is no more than a sum of particular wills.  [4]

What then is the character of the  general will  is more precisely defined in his essay  A Discourse on Political Economy  where he writes,

The body politic,  therefore,  is also a corporate being,  possessed of a will;  and this general will,  which tends always to the preservation and welfare of the whole and of every part,  and is the source of the laws,  constitutes for all the members of the State,  in their relations,  to one another and to it,  the rule of what is just or unjust.  [5]

In this citation we have the sense of something more than a corporate entity.  It has the sense of a living body with a consciousness that at one point he refers to as being the mind of the Deity as expressed by the  general will.  This is of course reminiscent of the theological conception of the nation,  as well as Hegel’s  National Mind.  The precise designation made in the citation above refers to two constituent elements in the  body politic.  On the one hand there are  “their relations to one another “,  and on the other there is the relation  ” to it “.  The two notions are joined with an  “and”  so providing a prelude to the Hegelian concept of the Nation-State.  It would be easy to note that the concept of civil society here corresponds to the notion of  ” their relations to one another “,  while the State would be best described by the reference  ” to it “.  The reference to  “the whole ”  and then  “of every part ”  seems to confirm this distinction.  This concept of the  body politic  contains both a reference to the State and an allusion to the nation.  This is however a difficult matter to determine with precision since the format of  The Social Contract  is based on the model of the Athenian  Polis.  At that time,  when the European cultures had not yet become sufficiently populated to constitute a national society,  and had not yet had the historical experience to bond into a nation,  the national concept did not serve as a useful idea to incorporate into the prevailing social structure.  The degree to which Rousseau would do so rests moreso in the subconscious,  although the complex of existing social relations would have provided him with the elaborated concept of  general will  that he has expressed.

            The civic conception of nation is limited in its significance as a result.  This public domain is mainly concerned with the nature of representation in the nation,  but not the nation per se.  To the extent that Rousseau distinguishes the nation from the State,  the nation is considered to be of greater significance. 

           In fact, does not the undertaking entered into by the whole body of the nation bind it  to provide for the security of the least of its members with as much care as for that of all the rest?  Is the welfare of a single citizen any less the common cause than that of the whole State?  [6]

The State is here sacrificed instead of the nation,  rather than violate the  ” fundamental laws of society”.  Society then cannot be considered equivalent to the State,  or its laws. 

For the fundamental conventions being broken,  it is impossible to conceive of any right or interest that could retain the people in the social union;  unless they were restrained by force,  which alone causes the dissolution of the state of civil society.  [7]

In this manner, the civil society is closely identified with the nation.  The fundamental law / conventions are the Social Contract,  otherwise considered to be the social constitution.  The People is taken as a synonym for Nation when there is a distinction to be made from the State,

the  body of the State,  …  we shall see that it will at length be reduced to a small number of persons,  who are not the people,  but the officers of the people  [8]

Despite the integral conception of the people provided, however,  the people or Nation,  are considered individually,  without a collective identity,  apart from their particular general will.  The particular wills found within the body politic are not identified as nationalities.  In this way,  the civic conception of the nation is based in the individual and their liberties alone.

2.         The  Ethnic  Conception  of  Nation

            Hegel seems to have a commonality for the State with Rousseau although they differ in its conception;

The philosophical treatment of these topics is concerned only with their inward side,  with the thought of their concept.  The merit of Rousseau’s contribution to the search for this concept is that,  by adducing the will as the principle of the state,  he is adducing a principle which has thought both for its form and its content,  a principle indeed which is thinking itself,  not a principle,  like gregarious instinct,  for instance,  or divine authority,  which has thought as its form only.  Unfortunately,  however,  as Fichte (4) did later,  he takes the will only in a determinate form as the individual will,  and he regards the universal will not as the absolutely rational element in the will,  but only as a  ‘general’  will which proceeds out of this individual will as out of a conscious will.  The result is that he reduces the union of individuals in the state to a contract and therefore to something based on their arbitrary wills,  their opinion,  and their capriciously given express consent;  and abstract reasoning proceeds to draw the logical inferences which destroy the absolutely divine principle of the state,  together with its majesty and absolute authority.  For this reason,  when these abstract conclusions came into power they afforded for the first time in human history the prodigious spectacle of the overthrow of the constitution of a great actual state and its complete reconstruction  ab initio  on the basis of pure thought alone, after the destruction of all existing and given material.  The will of its re-founders was to give it what they alleged was a purely rational basis,  but it was only abstractions that were being used; the Idea was lacking;  and the experiment ended in the maximum of frightfulness and terror. (5) [9]

The Idea lacking was the Nation according to Hegel.  Hegel discounts the state-Republic described by Rousseau as reduced to the format of a contract alone among various individual wills, which Hegel equates to the State.  This misrepresentation, or lack of appreciation of Hegel’s discounts the character of the  general will   which is described by Rousseau as greater than the sum of its parts.  Furthermore it is not at all clear that the  general will   was to be taken as the conception introduced for the purpose of describing the State alone.  It is actually more appropriate to conceive of it being ascribed to the Civil Society,  which has to be fundamentally differentiated from the State.  This would fundamentally alter Hegel’s conception of the State as the fusion of Form and Content since the Nation as Form coexists with its content Civil Society .

            Hegel himself very precisely does demarcate the character of the Civil Society;

188.    Civil Society contains three moments:

(A)       The mediation of need and one man’s satisfaction through his work and the satisfaction of the needs of all others — the System of Needs.

(B)       The actuality of the universal principle of freedom therein contained — the protection of property through the Administration of Justice.

(C)       Provision against contingencies still lurking in systems (A) and (B), and care for particular interests as a common interest, by means of the Police and the Corporation[10]

            While ignoring the fullest conception of the   general will   on the part of Rousseau,  Hegel contains a conception of Civil Society that is very elaborate in terms of the economic and personal spheres of activity in Civil Society. 

            Taking into account the confused interchanges he makes between Society and the Nation,  it could be said that Hegel goes beyond Rousseau in respect to Civil Society by presenting the epistemological basis for the Nation as being a reciprocal consciousness of common needs,  a conception lacking in Rousseau.  In Rousseau it is the State that limits the inherent divisiveness of Civil Society being as it is,  in his conception,  based in the particular wills of its citizenry.  Hegel’s exegesis of Kant and Rousseau’s statism goes beyond the Content of Civil Society to incorporate the nation integrally.

           The crucial point in both the Kantian and the generally accepted definition of right (see the introduction to Kant’s Philosophy of Law) (66) is the ‘ restriction which makes it possible for my freedom or self-will to coexist with the self-will of each and all according to a universal law ‘.  On the one hand, this definition contains only a negative category,  restriction,  while on the other hand the positive factor  —  the universal law or the so-called  ‘ law of reason’,  the correspondence of the self-will of one individual with that of another  —  is tantamount to the principle of contradiction and the familiar notion of abstract identity.  The definition of right which I have quoted involves;  that way of looking at the matter,  especially popular since Rousseau, (67) according to which what is fundamental, substantive, and primary is supposed to be the will of a single person in his own private self-will,  not the absolute or rational will,  and mind as a particular individual,  not mind as it is in its truth.  Once this principle is adopted,  of course the rational can come on the scene only as a restriction on the type of freedom which this principle involves,  and so also not as something immanently rational but only as an external abstract universal.  This view is devoid of any speculative thinking and is repudiated by the philosophic concept.  And the phenomena which it has produced both in men’s heads and in the world (68) are of a frightfulness parallel only to the superficiality of the thoughts on which they are based.

____________________

67.      See e.g. Contract Social, i. 6, where the  ‘ fundamental problem ‘  is said to be  ‘ to find a form of association which will defend and protect the person and property of each associate, and wherein each member, united to all the others, still obeys himself alone, and retains his original freedom ‘.  i.e. what is fundamental is the single individual and his natural liberty;  the task of the state is merely to protect these.   [11]

The individual however is fundamental only  in itself   and not  for itself   since the human species is a social being and really only finds fulfillment in the recognition received and the benefits derived in the collectivity.  The individual human is only such   in itself   and only becomes human actually when it is   for itself ,  by releasing its potential in the social context.  Freedom of speech,  for example,  is only possible if there is someone to hear.  Freedom then is a function of society and not the individual per se.

            Hegel continues to present a conception of society,  the nation together with the state;  these facets of political existence are considered to be united in the same process even though  they had been presented as developing in different manners.

The expansion of the family,  as its transition into a new principle,  is in the external world sometimes its peaceful expansion until it becomes a people,  i.e. a nation,  which this has a common natural origin,  or sometimes the federation of scattered groups of families under the influence of an overlord’s power  [a State – W]  or as a result of a voluntary association produced by the tie of needs and the reciprocity of their satisfaction  [a Society – W]. [12]

In his paragraphs numbered 341 and 344,  Hegel makes precise distinctions in reference to the nation and to civil society.  The differentiation between the two is presented in the following terms;

It is therefore

(A)      ethical mind in its natural or immediate phase — the Family.  This substantiality loses its unity,  passes over into division,  and into the phase of relation,  i.e. into

(B)      Civil Society — an association of members as self-subsistent individuals in a universality which,  because of their self-subsistence,  is only abstract.  Their association is brought about by their needs,  by the legal system — the means to security of person and property — and by an external organization for attaining their particular and common interests.  This external state

(C)      is brought back (18) to and welded into unity in the Constitution of the State which is the end and actuality of both the substantial universal order and the public life devoted thereto.  [13]

Civil Society is thus defined,  even though it rests imbedded with the notion of universality  derived from the assumption of national homogeneity,  and although it is also considered as naturally dependent upon the State as an external organization.  Rousseau seems to avoid this pitfall by elaborating his general will into a conception for civil society and bypassing the concept of nation.

            Hegel merely incorporates the nation into the state by definition;

#70     mind has become the state — the mind of a nation objectified in its rational and organic institutions. [14]

In this manner Hegel combines the civic conception of Rousseau’s and his own organic conception into one,  that of the State.  Nonetheless Hegel marks out two components of the State;  the  “rational”  and the  “organic”  institutions.    It would seem then that the  rational  refers to the State institutions,  and the

organic  refers to the national  institutions of Civil Society.  It is the Civil Society that is incorporated into the State superstructure.  This is the nature of the Hegelian Nation-State.  The institutions of the remaining Nations do not have access to the State institutions as a result unless they can demonstrate their utility by upholding that Nation-State.

3.         The  Evolution  of  the  Civic  and  Organic  Concepts

            Theories of nationalism are divided by their definition of the nation.   Stalin and Lenin’s famous and oft-quoted point criteria was seemingly patterned to define the Nation.  These various formalist criteria amounted to one operative principle,

Thus, [according to Stalin — GS] a common economic life, economic cohesion, is one of the characteristic features of a nation. 6

                        _________

6.        Stalin, Joseph  Marxism and the Nation-Colonial Question,  Proletarian Publishers,  San Francisco, 1975,  p. 20 [15]

The economic system of capitalism was considered the unifying force of nation building,  and in effect  the nation became a bourgeois phenomenon according to that paradigm.  This economic determinist model actually pertains to the State formation that it has mistaken for the nation itself because of the adoption of the Hegelian conception of Nation-State.. 

            Apart from the formal criteria as to what constitute a Nation,  the principle of nationality is essentially that a  People  which has a sense of self-recognition,  is the only fundamental criterion.  Herder’s attitude was that  “A Volk is virtually any group that has a name and a culture.” [16]   Gerry Sperling notes that;

Stalin realized that there was something intangible about nationhood,  as well,  something which he referred to as  national character  in quotation marks and which he summed up as   . . .  a common psychological makeup,  which manifests itself in a common culture . . .  7

                        __________

                        7.                     Ibid.,  p. 22  [17]

            In considering the various discussions of the nation,  evidently the lack of coherency on the subject results from the varying treatments of the same concept,  so as to be reconciled with the ideological predisposition of the writer.

Nous avons constaté qu’à travers l’histoire de l’étude de la question nationale, chez les marxists comme chez les non-marxists,  s’étaient peu à peu distinguées la question de l’État et celle de la nation comme groupe spécifique. [18]

Although such a distinction is made in one instance here by Bourque,  there is still a general tendency to treat the nation as a bourgeois creation identified with the State,  tending to annul the nation in the form of a People as a consideration.

            The Polish-Canadian academic Kawczak treats the nation as a specific entity apart from the State;

The concept of nation

What constitutes a nation?  There are two ways to define the concept of nation.  One is to identify a nation as the people who live on a territory under the same supreme political authority.  In other words,  a nation is the population of a state.  This definition emphasizes the political rather than the sociological aspect.

           The other,  more sociological way to define a notion is to identify it with what is meant by nationality.  Usually,  nationality is defined as an enduring community of people bound by common origin, fate, culture, language, territory and economic connections.  All these bonds normally give rise to a consciousness of belonging together,  of having a common “national identity”.  This feeling of national identity is sometimes so strong that a community may aspire to be considered a nation even if it is not politically organized as a separate and independent state.

           From the standpoint of nationalism the identification of nation with nationality seems to make more sense than the view that strictly binds the concept of nation to a state.  [19]

While the nation is here described by an accumulation of characteristics these need not be taken as obligatory.  Kawczak’s philosophical conceptualization is more to the point than the sociological references he makes,  as well. 

            In contrast, the standard interpretation by Marxist thought on  the national question  falters on the proposition that the Nation is given expression by a State superstructure,  that is,  the Hegelian conception. 

4.         National Minorities in the Modern Conceptions

                        Let us continue with the analysis of nation-State.  Hegel presents the earliest expression of this formulation that my readings have uncovered,

#331   The nation state is mind in its substantive rationality and immediate actuality and is therefore the absolute power on earth. [20]

This formulation unveils the illness derived from Herder which equates the nation with the State,  in the sense that the State is formed to encompass one and only one nation.  While this may be essential to the  Hegelian conception of State it is nonetheless not an accurate reflection of Society.  In order to resolve the contradiction with the State at large,  it is presumed that the Society comprises just one nationality and that other national social formations are nonexistent,  by way of redefinition into some other catagory such as that of a religion or language grouping only.  The proposition for assimilation into the dominant Nation and its State is the problematic. 

            It is this abstraction of the Nation-State that sets up a false image of the Society,  that comprises a false consciousness,  and that ends by being in contradiction with the actuality.  And it is the actual that is real and not that ideology. 

            Following from his presumption,  Hegel is led into hierarchy when different rights are counterpoised:

Yet at the same time collision involves another moment,  namely the fact that it is restrictive,  and so if two rights collide one is subordinated to the other.  It is only the right of the world-mind which is absolute without qualification. [21]

The practice of priority in the collision of rights is followed in Hegelian society between nationalities where basically the matter of the interaction of wills,  and in particular,  the interaction of a will and its other is in question.  It is the role of the State to subordinate one will to the other, but there is no basis in theory to subordinate the other to the one,  or the one to the other.  The choice to subordinate one or the other to its negative is a special interest preference and not a function of necessity,  unless we are to consider self-determination a necessity as defined by the interests of one special interest.  The priority of the State,  or its  divine right,  is tied to the existing source of power seeking to maintain its own stability by means of the State.  This is far from the needs of a society.  Consequently,  the role of the State is distinct from that of the national communities,  and for the same reason the State is evidently an impediment to a minority nation’s expression as an  autonomous national-cultural collective will.

5.         The   Liberal   Democratic   State

            The Liberal theory of social management assumes the perpetuation of social contradictions and seeks to limit or restrict their effects by legal mechanisms designed by the political authority and carried out by the judicial apparatus defending the liberal principle of limitations.

            The Liberal social theory is further constrained by the legal definition of an entity being solely the individual,  and the reproductive collectivity only being the family as headed by the male individual.  That individual,  the head of the household ,  is a vestige of the propertied and patriarchal definition of the person that excluded women, servants, slaves, and foreigners.  This idea of equality by individuality is maintained in contradiction to the collectivity of nationality.  The individual is placed in opposition to the collectivity,  and  collective rights are negated by the priority placed upon the individual rights currently in effect.  Collective national rights are consequently in contradiction to the State,  as has been revealed in the Canadian context.  Recognition of the existence of nationalities other than the officially recognized State nationality is thus treated as illegal though there may be two official languages.  In effect language is dissociated from the national culture from which it arose.

            Collective rights are interpreted according to ideology,  and Stuart Rush comments on their constitutional application in Canada. 

There are two ways in which collective rights can be perceived constitutionally.  First,  collective rights are those rights which accrue to individuals because of their placement or membership in an identifiable group.  In this sense,  the realisation of the rights for each individual depends on its realisation for everyone in the group.  These are the rights of cultural communities, ethnic and minority groups.  They include the working people of Canada.  These rights are rooted in history and represent a benefit or protection to the group as a whole.  These would include:  the right to employment;  the rights of ethnic minorities to use their languages and to practise certain traditions;  and the right to participate in government.  Second,  collective rights are also rights which accrue to groups as groups.  These include:  the right of Indian people to title to and jurisdiction over their aboriginal land;  and the right of women to affirmative action programmes in the workplace.  Group rights,  which insure the protection of a group, as a group, ought to have been provided for in the Constitution [of 1982 – A.W.].  [22]

            The limitations imposed by the liberal State are coached in the context of a morality proclaimed by a Theocracy.  Alternatively,  a collective autonomy of the various social formations in society could cooperate according to a methodology based in a Principle of Reciprocity.  In place of the rule of the Law,  operating on behalf of the State and its enforcers,  there may exist the cultural attributes of mutuality nurtured in civil jurisprudence,  as is the right of the citizen jury presently.

            The reliance upon the individual in liberal theory abstractly grants the utmost in personal liberty but fails to recognize the context in which the individual finds themselves,  whether that is a class context, a national identity or a particular gender. 

           Every political society is composed of other smaller societies of different kinds,  each of which has its interests and its rules of conduct:  but those societies which everybody perceives,  because they have an external and authorized form,  are not the only ones that actually exist in the State:  all individuals who are united by a common interest compose as many others,  either transitory or permanent,  whose influence is none the less real because it is less apparent,  and the proper observation of whose various relations is the true knowledge of public morals and manners.  The influence of all these tacit or formal associations causes,  by the influence of their will,  as many different modifications of the public will.  The will of these particular societies has always two relations;  for the members of the association,  it is a general will; for the great society,  it is a particular will;  and it is often right with regard to the first object,  and wrong as to the second.  An individual may be a devout priest, a brave soldier,  or a zealous senator,  and yet a bad citizen.  A particular resolution may be advantageous to the smaller community,  but pernicious to the greater.  It is true that,  particular societies always being subordinate to those that contain them,  the  latter should be obeyed rather than the former;  the duty of a citizen takes precedence of that of a senator,  and a man’s duty of that of a citizen:  but unhappily personal interest is always found in inverse ratio to duty,  and increases in proportion as association grows narrower,  and the engagement less sacred;  which irrefragably proves that the most general will is always the most just also,  and that the voice of the people is in fact the voice of God.  [23]

Rousseau provides us with a hierarchical version of pluralism because of the individualist criterion for civil society.

6.         The   Federal   Principle

                        The work of  Pierre-Joseph Proudhon  was concerned with the mutualist political current when he proposed a form of society that rejected the centralized State in favour of federal relations among the constituents of a country.  In writing to the editor of the journal L’Impartial  he insisted,  as cited by George Woodcock;

Why should we not invite the population to make themselves capable of managing their own affairs and of preparing the way for a confederation of peoples?  Let them see,  through instruction, science, moral health and patriotism, how to dispense with all ministerial and constitutional hierarchy,  while in the meantime profiting from the little good it will do them.  [24]

Proudhon’s biographer George Woodcock further interpretes this conception,

Thus the nation itself will be a confederation of regions,  and Europe a confederation of confederations in which the interest of the smallest province will have as much expression as that of the largest,  since all affairs will be settled by mutual agreement,  contract and arbitration.  [25]

The concept of confederation is obviously different from the current usage in Canada and should rather mean the mutual relations of autonomous social formations.  The mechanism of decision-making follows in the same vein through the proposal that a process of unanimity would be operational by the indicated mechanisms of mutuality.  Such political means can be augmented by the procedures followed in the Iroquois Confederation decision-making process which also is based upon a form of unanimity. 

            The compatibility of the Federal Principle and national formations is also alluded to above by Proudhon,  based as it is upon the differentiation between the Society and the State,  despite the deficiencies of Anarchist ideology with respect to the nation.

            In contrast,  Reg Whitaker mentions the Federal Principle in a presentation of state federalism that interprets the matter as a government of governments.  Concerning Canada and Québec he concludes with an appreciation of the  Constitution Act of 1982  as  “a reasonable compromise between a number of conflicting pressures.” [26]   Collective Rights as a nation are absent as such from his analysis of the superstructure. 

7.         The  Iroquois  Confederation

            The  Kaianere’ko:wa,  or  The Law of the Great Peace / The Great Law  is the traditionalist code of society before the influx of Europeans to this continent.  This constitutional law unified the five founding nations or tribes of northeast North America to become the  HAUDENOSAUNEE  or  The People of the Long House: Iroquois.  This initial united nations has also been called the  League of the Five,  or the  Iroquois Confederation.  It is this treaty that contributed to the elaboration of the constitution of the United States of America and the Confederation of Canada,  and may represents the oldest constitution still applied in the world.  [27]

            This  Great Binding Law [28]  was initially elaborated with the formation of the League of the Five Nations about the year 1390 and was transmitted in the inscriptions of the Wampum belts  —  coded beads forming symbolic designs  —  held by the women chiefs,  and coded strings for particular laws or paragraphs,  in addition to oral recitations,  until it was printed in more recent times.  This assembly of the various Peoples’ representatives was in effect an ancient Parliament that sat in discussion of any dispute serious enough to warrant the calling together of the delegates.

            According to the Iroquois Book of the Great Law,  the confederate Council was to consist of fifty rodiyaners  (civil chiefs)  and was to be divided into three bodies;  that is,  the older brothers;  Mohawk and the Seneca,  the younger brothers;  Cayuga and the Oneida,  and,  the fire keepers;  Onondaga.  Each brotherhood debated a question separately and reported to the fire keepers,  who referred the matter back and ordered a unanimous report.  If the two brotherhoods still disagreed, the fire keepers had the final decision.  If,  however,  the brotherhoods agreed and their decision was not in accord with the wishes of the fire keepers,  the fire keepers could only confirm the decision,  for  unanimity was the law required for the passage of any question.  Similarly the Council chooses to convene to consider any particular question presented to it,  acting in effect as a Supreme Court.  All the work of the Council was done without an executive head,  that is,  without a head of State or government,  such as a president or prime minister.  These fifty civil chiefs were nominated by certain noble women who carried a hereditary title in their family,  so elaborating a matrilineal society recognized officially as an electoral college;  nominations were confirmed by popular councils of both men and women,  and then finally by the confederate Council.  Women had not only the great power to nominate the rulers but also the power to depose them for incompetency in office.  Here,  then,  we find the right of popular nomination, recall and of women’s suffrage.[29]

            It is noteworthy that there is no mention of private property in the traditional documentation.  Land is considered to be a  given  that is,  existing in itself and not conferring special privileges upon a particular individual.  Territory held in common is inherent in the conception of a People or nation,  such as the Mohawk.  The idea of property in land is absent,  and land itself is thus treated as existing in the public domain.[30]

            In a parallel fashion we may remind ourselves that land came to be considered a common national resource during the course of the English revolution,  when Crown Lands became Common Land in the manner of a territorial nationalization.  

            The Inter-national perspective means the territorial integrity of the Native Peoples’ nations by the recognition of independent nations in polynational societies through reciprocal relations,  as in the theory of Federation. 

 

            A social formation that becomes a society may be based in a national-culture as it exists in reciprocity with other suchlike formations. Such a project is possible  through the mutual recognition represented in a common society amongst the major constituent nationalities, as well as the proportionally less populous nationalities. Consequently, the same methodology may be applied among the global societies and nations.

            The relations engendered by the various national cultures and their societies form the Inter and Intra-National dynamic of a resolution towards mutual recognition, reciprocal interchanges and mutual aid.  Currently imposed upon this social-formation is a superstructure of State institutions that constitute the International system of politics.  This defines the distinction between the terms  Inter-National [1] — concerning relations between Nations — and the term International that relates to the relations between States, as in the UNO (United Nations Organization). 

            Currently we see the  Fragmentation  of the State into various Nations that have retained their historic memory.  With the imposition of the State formation the equality of national status is compromised by the centralized nature of that structure and its accompanying cultural homogenization or dictatorship of a minority, or perhaps, a majority of the citizens.  The lack of collective rights within the State, in this manner, compromises the rights of the citizen to their national identity.   Minority national collectives in particular are hampered by the imposition of a majoritarian dictatorship (as in the Hobbesian sense).  This lack of national recognition results in the Fragmentation taking place at an accelerating pace throughout this century.

            As originally perceived in the  “Federal principle”,[31]  it is possible to conceive of Society as composed of various social formations that are nationally-autonomous.  As Proudhon did, this is to distinguish Society from the State, which can be loosely defined here as an exclusive property in territory that contains a certain population of individuals. 

            It is projected here that the nature of social representation may be altered to form a criteria of approval that is based upon a consensus of unanimity amongst the various social formations rather than simply majoritarianism  ( or democracy as it is named ).  The social process that is unanimity takes root in the collective network of social formations based in their particular autonomous social orientation.  Unanimity becomes the ongoing series of negotiations for the allocation of scarce resources and the development of the means to supply the social needs that are projected.  The lack of particular resources gives rise to an increased momentum towards global societal interaction engendering an Inter-National climate of exchange in resources, technology, nationalities, and information.

8.         The Crisis of Canada

            In the June-July 1977 issue of the journal  Canadian ForumA Proposal For a New Constitution  presented by  The Committee For a New Constitution  appeared.  Despite the proposals for a popularly elected constitutional assembly,  this project has not been possible and seems unlikely until the Québécoise (Kébékoiz)  nation achieves its autonomy or independence from the State of Canada. 

            This proposal for the drafting of a social constitution to be ratified by submission to the public is based in the preeminence of the civil society over the State apparatus.  This concept isunlike the previous experiences in formulating a constitution when the central State was dominant.  The British North America Act was legalized per saltum (in one leap) without debate by the Imperial government in collusion with the dependent Canadian elite and the Québec Catholic Church apparatus.  With even the admonition of the Bishop of Rimouski that:

‘You will respect this new constitution that is given you as the expression of the supreme will of the legislator,  of the legitimate authority,  and consequently that of God Himself.’  [32]

the Québec electorate returned 20 opposition members to 40 government supporters.  The constitution of 1982 was not even submitted for public approval since the government of Québec itself did not approve it. 

            In contrast the methodology presented by the Canadian Forum proposal presented here anticipates that upon the,

event that Quebec chooses independence with association,  the rest of Canada should be in a position to propose terms of association.  …  [by means of]  the creation of a popularly elected constituent assembly charged with drafting a new constitution   . . .   including provision for terms of association with Quebec  (in the event that Quebec should so opt)  which would then be submitted to public ratification. [33]

Such a process would undoubtedly transform English-speaking Canada as much as Québec would be changing.  Considering the lack of viable current proposals being presented on behalf of a united Canada it seems that we are both moving into a period of mutual transformation.  No doubt English-speaking Canda is less prepared to do so,  however it is not in a position to be able to impose its will to the contrary,  considering that the population of Québec comprises some 27-29% of the general population.

            What has not been considered is the extent of the influence that is to be felt by the Kébékois(ze) nation.  While this nation comprises only 80% of the province of Québec itself,  the Kébekois(ze) reside throughout the rest of Canada and in the United States as well.  This national identification poses political questions about the nature of society in general.  If there is to be a pluralist political culture then evidently it will have to include the collective identity and rights of the Kébékois(ze) national minority.  And if the Kébékois(ze) achieve their national collective identity then other national minorities will seek to do so as well,  as have the indigenous native peoples.  Not only  is such a pluralist political agenda posed in Canada,  it is also posed for the U.S.A. within which the national minorities of African-Americans / New Africans,  Puerto Rico, Hawaii, Spanish-speaking Americans as well as Native peoples will find the example of the new Kébèk [2] to be appealing.

 

Notes


     [1]         O’Sullivan See, K.                               The Social Origins of Ethnic-National Identities in Ireland and Canada,

                                                               pgs. 107 – 129,

                                                               National and Ethnic Movements, ed. Jacques Dofny and Akinsola Akiwowo,                                                                SAGE Studies in International Sociology 19,

                                                               International Sociological Associates, Beverly Hills & London, 1980,  p. 121

     [2]         Cole, G.D.H.                        Introduction,  pgs. xi – xliv

                                                               The Social Contract  and  Discourses,  Jean-Jacques Rousseau

                                                               Dent, London, 1975 ,  p. xxix

     [3]         Cole                                       ibid.,  p. xliii

     [4]         Rousseau,  J-J                      The Social Contract  and  Discourses

                                                               Dent, London, 1975,  p. xxxii

     [5]         Rousseau                             ibid.

                                                               A Discourse on Political Economy,  pgs. 117 – 153,  p. 120-121

     [6]         Rousseau                             ibid.,  p. 132

     [7]         Rousseau                             ibid.,  p. 132

     [8]         Rousseau                             ibid.,  p. 132

     [9]         Hegel, G.F.W.                      Philosophy of Right

                                               Oxford University Press, London, (1942) 1949,  p. 156

     [10]        Hegel                                     op.  cit.,  p. 126

     [11]        Hegel                     op. cit.,  p. 33

     [12]        Hegel                                     op. cit.,  p. 122

     [13]        Hegal                                    op. cit.,  p. 110, para.  #157

     [14]        Hegel                                     op. cit.,  p. 33,  para. #70

     [15]        Sperling, Gerry                     Prolegomena for a discussion of socialism and the National Question

                                                               Socialist Studies Conference, Kingston, Ontario

                                                               University of Regina, June 1, 1991,  p. 3

     [16]        Manuel, Frank E.                               Introduction to  Reflections on The Philosophy of the History of Mankind

                                                               by Johann Gottfried von Herder

                                                               University of Chicago Press, 1968,  p. xiv

     [17]        Sperling, Gerry                     op. cit.,  p. 3

     [18]        Bourque                                               op. cit.,  p. 55

“We have insisted that throughout the history of the study of the national question that it was the case that little by little, both among the Marxists and the non-Marxists, that the State was distinguished from that of the Nation as a specific group.”

     [19]        Kawczak, A.                        Nationalism, Mental Health and Human Development,  pgs. 231 – 253

                                                               Mental Health in a Changing World, ed. Brunon Holyst

                                                               The Polish Society for Mental Health, Warsaw, 1990,  p. 236 – 7

     [20]        Hegel                                     op.  cit.,  p. 212,  para. #331

     [21]        Hegel                                     op. cit.,  p. 33,  para. #70

     [22]        Rush, Stewart                      Collective Rights and Collective Process: 

                                                               Missing Ingredients in the Canadian Constitution

                                                               Socialist Studies/Études Socialistes: 

                                                               A Canadian Annual no.2, 1984,  p. 1 – 2

     [23]        Rousseau                             op. cit.,  p. 121-122

     [24]        Woodcock                           Pierre-Joseph Proudhon :  A Biography

                                                               Black Rose Books, Montreal, New York, 1987,  p. 21

     [25]        Woodcock                           ibid.,  p. 249

     [26]        Whitaker, Reg                     Democracy, Federalism and the

                                                               National Political Communities in Canada

                                                               Socialist Studies/Études Socialistes: 

                                                               A Canadian Annual No. 2, 1984,  p. 11

     [27]        Weizfeld, eibie                     Native People’s Law Code,  pgs. 374 – 375

                                                               Reader’s Digest Legal Problem Solver

                                                               Brott, Nelson, ed.

                                                               The Reader’s Digest Association (Canada) Ltd., Montreal, 1994

     [28]        Kaianere’ko:wa:

                La “Grand Bien”                 Pleine  Terre, Vol. I No. 1, Solstice d’été, 1992

     [29]        Parker, A.C.                         The Constitution of the Five Nations or

                                                               The Iroquois Book of the Great Law,

                                                               Iroqrafts Ltd., Ohsweken, Ontario, Canada, 1984 (1916)

     [30]        Kaianere’ko:wa: 

                Le ‘Grand Bien’                 op. cit.

     [31]        Proudhon,

                Pierre-Joseph                       The Federal Principle

                                                               University of Toronto Press, Toronto

     [32]        Dowson,  Ross                     Quebec & the Canada Crisis:

                                                               for a Constituent Assembly and a new Canadian Constitution., 

                                                               Forward Publications,  Toronto,  October 1977,  p. 4

     [33]        Dowson, Ross                      ibid.,  p. 14 – 16


[1].         see paper prepared for use at the International Studies Association Conference in Chicago, February 22-25, 1995 by Fred W. Riggs, Professor Emeritus, Political Science Department, University of Hawaii, entitled:

                        TURMOIL AMONG NATIONS,  A CONCEPTUAL ESSAY:

                        Ethnonationalism, Authoritarianism, Anarchy, and Democracy

                        p. 10

[2].         this term is based in the original name for the territorial around the waterways entering the North American continent given to the original French settlers by the Algonkin nation.

My Sabra-Shatila Memoir

2013/11/30

My Sabra-Shatila Memoir

2012-09-13
Montréal
dr. abraham Weizfeld
~~~~
Being settled in Ottawa, after leaving my post of university lecturer at York University’s Social and Political Thought Department and Political Science Department, I found myself on Papineau Street in Hull across the river from Ottawa and the Palestine Information Office of the Arab League.
The information office substituted for the Palestine Embassy since Palestine did not exist for the government of Canada, in spite of the 1948 Partition Plan, which specifically called for its formation in the lands to be divided with the Zionist State. A telephone call from the Director-Ambassador Abdullah Abdullah was sufficient form me to leave Toronto and become an assistant writer during the first Israel invasion of Lebanon in 1982. Surely this was a decision made with the attention of Yasser Arafat with whom I had had an argument in 1980 during the international solidarity conference in Beirut in 1980. Not so much as an argument as a disagreement and not so much a disagreement as a shock when Arafat shouted “No” to the request for a message to the Jewish People. However in 1982 I came to work as a writer in the small two room ‘Embassy’.
Beginning with letters to the editors of the three key newspapers in Canada; the Toronto Daily Star, the Ottawa Citizen and the Montreal Gazette, many of the letters sent out were published as letters to the editor under various names. Soon enough there were counter letters that appeared to be a public debate with the Israel Embassy. However when the news came out of the massacre taking place in Sabra-State refugee camps of Beirut, I was overwhelmed with the deluge of information that came out of the New York Times, Newsweek, The Economist, Village Voice, WAFA (Palestinian News Agency), as well as the Canadian papers. The information was more detailed than any reports previously about the Palestinians. Although I was assigned to write a thirty-page report on Sabra-Shatila, there available information was so damning of the Phalange and Israel forces that it seemed inevitable that the information would be covered up over time. Making the report comprehensive so that this massacre would not be forgotten, I continued to condense the event into a 115-page work.
Three months and five drafts later typed on a manual non-electric typewriter, the resultant book remained unpublished for months even while the Sabra-Shatila massacre led to the largest demonstration in Israeli history of 500,000 and which resulted in the Oslo accords, to calm the revulsion that arose with the exposure of the facts of 3000 being slaughtered over three days with little resistance after the 5000 fighters of Arafat had been deported to Tunisia, with the promise by the USA that the refugees would be protected!
While the Arab League would not publish the work under the name of Abdullah Abdullah, the now defunct Palestinian ‘Jerusalem International Publishing House’ did take it on and put it out under my name as writer and with an introduction by the Arab League Director Yassar Askari. ‘Sabra and Shatila’ was published unfortunately with a subtitle that sought to exploit the Holocaust upon the insistence of the publisher, Ahmed Murad. The second edition has been published since, during 2009. with subsequent documentation and is found at the site:
Sabra & Shatila (1984) 2009
http://bookstore.authorhouse.com/AdvancedSearch/Default.aspx?SearchTerm=weizfeld

Cotler critique

2013/11/30

De: abraham Weizfeld [saalaha@fokus.name]
1. Envoyé: 3 février 2011 18:38
Objet: AW RE: Prof. Irwin Cotler about Jewish Refugees from Arab States

I just listened to the Cotler interview on Jewish refugees. I am familiar with the argument but he helps to clarify what the Zionist parties are trying to make of it.
I was raised a Bundist and not a Zionist by my refugee mother from Warsaw and so do not succumb to the Zionist ideologues like Cotler, who seek to make hay out of the Jewish-Arab refugees who sought their security in Israel and received a second class of citizenship, just like the Dimmini status in the Arab countries that they hoped to escape.
The intellectual errors he makes are;
1) his historical myopia is not able to focus on the fact that the Palestinians refugees were created in the military occupation of their villages in the war of 1947-48, even before the Arab military forces intervened to halt the Zionist militias advance to the Green Line which lasted until 1967 when the State of Israel expanded once again to the Jordan river. These 750,000 refugees now number up to 7 million 63 years later,
2) The Jewish refugees from the Arab countries who came to Israel later in the 1950’s, they were being discriminated against because of their Zionist affiliations and so are also victims of the Zionist policies that so alienated the Arab political culture. While many Jewish-Arab citizens stayed put many chose to seek certain rights and privileges in Israel. No doubt the refugees here had been subject to minority discrimination, There is some claims that violence was used to expel them and that their goods were confiscated or sold at rates less than the market value, although the sums may be minor considering the lack of documentation on the matter. In any case many of the Arab countries offer the right of return fro those Jewish-Arabic refugees. There are also instances of violence being used by Zionist agents to induce the flow of refugees as well as in their subsequent treatment by Israel in terms of stolen gold jewlarry of Yemenites and irradiation of Mizrachi children’s heads. I have helped the Sepharads to publicize this last case in Canada.
3) Cotler also makes a virtue of the Jewish refugees and while neglecting the Palestinian refugees, as if they were not refugees. They still are living as such due to the local population’s less numerous status making their integration problematic and yet discriminatory,
4) and yet while calling for the permanent integration of Palestinian refugees, Israel has intervened in Jordan to suppress the Palestinian revolt and in Lebanon to maintian their exclusion. The contradiction is obvious.
5) etc.

Direct and Parallel Democracy

2013/11/30

Direct and Parallel Democracy
Social Programme for Kébèk
(13/04/1999 revised 21/04/1999 en français)

(Annex of the political document
« Nations in the inter-national context »
article published in the revue POSSIBLES, No. 1999 )

Document 1
The Constitution of Civil Society

In recognition of the diversity of peoples that are increasingly seeking out each other’s culture and societies we have come to the proposition that this migratory feature of human existence has always been a feature of our social life.
Recent decades seemingly continue to demonstrate this dynamic and so provide the conclusive convulsion in the decline of the Hegelian Nation-State of Europe fame. Despite the continued efforts to subjugate the lands of others, the degree of hegemony necessary to continue to gather public support and military sacrifices to bear this out, is lacking. The international anti-war movement has gone beyond the pacifistic morality and has reached the fundamentals for the perpetuation of war, the military-industrial complex and the sovereign State which only seeks to perpetuate itself in lieu of the Monarch. This is only the Monarch in disguise. The disguise is what is named Democracy. The Occidental world, the West continues to claim this word as its prerogative and upholds itself as the prime model of this great achievement. And yet it is known that Athens was of the Oriental world at the time and provides the West with the model it claims to emulate. The Orient has much more to offer for those who care to look. The Western style of parliamentary democracy is the diminution of the Monarch but not its abolition. This is precisely what the USA President means by Presidential prerogative as Head of State including the Military. He claims the right to make war in contradiction to the Constitution of its Constituent Assembly. That revolutionary Assembly set the Civil Society into motion in opposition to governance by the United Kingdom until is has come into conflict with its State.
The social Orders in the hierarchy defined by the State itself have only been surpassed by the emerging Civil Societies in each country. Having been exposed to the Parliamentary Monarchy the Libyan society has taken hold of itself and away from its liberal democratic Monarchy. There the people have undertaken to govern themselves through Peoples Assemblies in their places of residence and work. Political life is as if there were and permanent Constituent Assembly always maintaining sovereignty in itself and not ascribing or abrogating it to any other power other than that of the People.
Not only is this direct democracy befit the original conception as announced by Pericles, but it has become a necessity considering the increasing number of failed States. The fracturization of the State is a phenomenon of these times and marks the end of the State. Civil Society in its own right has come to assert itself as an actual Society in the “Jamahiriya” as it is known, something like social solidarity.
The proposition here is one to tailor-make this Civil Society onto the Peoples of Kebek and in particular what is know as the Kébèkois (Québécois) society.
The ambiguity here is that there is to a common assumption made by a tendency of thought in the majoritarian culture which defines itself as a Nation. The issue then is how to reconcile the legitimate interests of the majoritarian Nation together with that of each of the minority nationalities, in particular the First Nations, of Aboriginal Peoples. Taking into consideration that the original Constitution of the Five (Six) Nations founded in 1390 is still in operation there is no doubt that there is a need for a reciprocal relation that need be formulated to satisfy the conditions of democratic life.
Taking the “Jamahiriya” as an example of the political theory of the “Green Book” for example the organizational principle is the basic People’s Assembly where each person comes to vote and to make propositions.
Here is an outline of what a Kébèkois society would function like;

1. Minority Nationalities

1.1 Recognizing that an independent Kébèkois society is a pluralist formation comprising of the majority francophone Nation;
1.2 and that the common public language is French;
1.3 it is also recognized that the languages of minority cultures are also means of communication amongst the minority peoples;
1.4 in considering that the minority nationalities — designated under the names of “cultural minorities”, “ethnic minorities”, “ethniccultures” or otherwise — they are social collectivities and shall be accorded the status and the rights as such, being recognized as nations;
1.5 among others, it is here reiterated that the First Nations exercise their right to auto-determination in respect to language, education, economics and territory, up to and including the right to independence;
1.6 it is also recognized that national minorities have the right to be autonomous, all in respect to the right of auto-determination of the Kébèkois Nation.

2. Social Structure

2.1 Considering the necessity of organizing the Kébèkois Civil Society, it becomes necessary to build an upper House which reflects and defends the interests of the population distinct from the general interests of the State;
2.2 recognizing that the civil society is composed of diverse social bodies reflecting the complex internetworkings between social classes, the nationalities, the genders and the generations;

3. Organizational Formations

3.1 Considering that the neo-liberal parties have usurped the “sovereignty” of the people in the interests of one power bloc or another,
3.2 and that the social movements have given form to an independent civil society in Québec;
3.3 recognizing that each movement and social formation remains an independent body;
3.4 it is proposed here that each and every such social body constitute itself into Assembly to enable its delegates to join in the General Constituent Assembly which will give rise to a permanent Peoples Congress including representation from the constituent bodies of Civil Society to carry forward the decisions of those basic bodies so that a consensus may be arrived at on a proportional basis;
3.5 the purpose of which is to preserve the multiple identities of the various minorities which amount to the Society as a whole.

Document 2

Geographical Distribution

4. Socio-geographical distribution

4.1 According to the range of identities among social formations and in particular nationalities it is presumed that any one individual member of society seeks to represent themselves in the various assemblies with which they would identify with such as place of residence, area of work, gender, and/or nationality;
4.2 so that within each such social formation there is a geographical alignment as well such that each social formation seeks to form its assemblies in each geographical locality as well as assembly in plenary;
4.3 accordingly each such formation replicates itself both in its localities together with a general social conglomeration thus forming parallel entities which interact from the local district to the social level as well;
4.4 beginning with the local basic people’s assembly in each sense already referred to the propositions formulated by those assemblies are carried to the regional and social assemblies by the elected and recallable Secretariats which are the constituent elements of the General People’s Congress;
4.5 it being understood that the proposition which arise in the delegated bodies composed of the Secretariats are responsible to the basic People’s Assemblies and do not only refer their deliberations to the Assemblies to which they delegate to;
4.6 that the process of deliberation is required to arrive at a consensus of opinion and interests to the extent that social planning in general, is referred to the Basic People’s Assemblies for ratification.

5. Regional Distribution

5.1 It is the task of the Constituent Assembly to agree upon the regional distribution of the Basic People’s Assemblies which may or may not correspond to the riding association of the current electoral commissions;
5.2 such a distribution of Assemblies over a geographical context would respect the regional identities such as the Gaspezie, the North Shore, the Sageney, the Bosh region around Québec, the Eastern Townships, the Laurentides, the Grand Nord and Montréal with its Montregie;
5.3 within each region there being the natural sociological associations with territory that represent the various First Nations which give rise to intermediatory assemblies;
5.4 together with the various neighbourhood identities that correspond to the various nationalities that reside in the metropolitan areas which also give rise to intermediatory assemblies;
5.5 each and every assembly may chose to provide translation services in reciprocity with the particular language that is common to the members of that assembly in addition to the common French language of Society;
5.6 all of which provides for what may be termed a Federation of Federations.
5.7

LES NATIONS DANS LE CONTEXTE INTER-NATIONAL

2013/11/30

APPENDIX H

LES NATIONS DANS LE CONTEXTE INTER-NATIONAL

par Abraham Weizfeld (v.3.6)
saalaha@fokus.name
novembre-décembre 1998

la revue POSSIBLES Volume 23, numéro 2, février 1999 printemps

La conception de la Nation d’un survivant de deuxième génération du génocide Nazi est très différente de celle qui peut prévaloir par exemple pour l’État américain.

La différence en terme de rapport au pouvoir est très claire, tout comme l’écart entre la réalité nationale de la plupart des petites Nations et ces États-Nations forteresses si courants aujourd’hui et qui font envie à la plupart des autres peuples. On peut penser par exemple, aux nations québécoises, kurdes, palestiniennes et juives, et à beaucoup d’autres. Celles qui bénéficient d’une continuité territoriale aspirent à la constitution d’une institution étatique qui représente leur Nation. D’autres, qui ne vivent pas à l’intérieur d’un territoire défini, peuvent
tout de même aspirer à instaurer une Terre commune, sur la base de laquelle ils deviendraient « une Nation semblable aux autres Nations ». La problématique qui découle de ces éléments est la question de la nature de la représentation de la Nation, et comment celle-ci touche ceux qui sont affectés de par leur proximité et ceux qui vivent à l’intérieur de la juridiction en question.
Cela nous amène au coeur de la fameuse dichotomie entre “le Moi et Autrui” et des tentatives jusque là apparemment vaines pour la résoudre.

D’ici l’an 2000, il est probable que les peuples Québécois et Palestiniens auront proclamé l’indépendance de leur État, réalisant ainsi la conception qu’ils ont d’eux-mêmes en tant que Nation. La quête de l’indépendance est le sujet de cet article, dans lequel je m’appuie en particulier sur l’exemple donné par le Peuple Juif au cours de sa lutte pour sa survie et son identité. Nous sommes aujourd’hui témoin de la volonté de l’État d’Israël de s’affirmer comme entité homogène au dépens de territoires habités par la Nation Palestinienne, devenue ainsi «les victimes parmi les victimes » selon l’expression d’Edward Said. Le problème ici vient de ce que l’État se pose comme un impératif, et présente sa raison d’être comme une idéologie, comme c’est le cas pour le Sionisme. Pourtant, dans l’histoire du Peuple Juif au cours du siècle dernier, le Sionisme n’a été qu’une des deux grandes tendances qui ont marqué sa culture politique. La seconde, qui est opposée à la première, est représentée par le Bund (Union générale des ouvriers juifs), lequel s’est constitué la même année que le Mouvement Sioniste, à savoir en 1897. Sa politique Bundist d’alors reflète les revendications territoriales de l’époque et la position du social-démocrate austro-hongrois Otto Bauer qui prenait la possibilité d’une autonomie culturelle et nationale pour la Nation Juive dans le cadre d’une société pluraliste. Sans tomber dans l’erreur de l’exclusivisme en identifiant l’une (la Nation) à l’autre (la Société), on peut déceler la Nation en émergence dans l’environnement social existant, côte à côte avec les autres communautés nationales, l’ensemble formant cette Société Civile particulière.

L’évolution du concept de Société autonome s’est nourrie des différentes expériences révolutionnaires au cours des siècles passés.

L’objectif d’établissement d’une Société Civile a été abandonné tant par les forces révolutionnaires qui cherchaient plutôt à s’emparer du pouvoir en remplaçant un État par un autre — que par les libéraux-démocrates, en substituant à la volonté générale sa représentation par un parti politique — et que par les révolutions nationales, qui ont laissé aux bourgeoisies nationales le pouvoir de représenter la Nation. Alors même que l’équivalence des concepts d’État et de Nation est affirmée comme évidente, la Société Civile, elle, a été ignorée et maintenue dans une situation de subordination par rapport à la superstructure étatique. Il est pourtant clair que c’est en fait la Société Civile elle-même qui abrite la Nation et permet sa survie. Il faut cependant être précis concernant le mode de formation d’une Nation indépendante à partir d’ une nébuleuse sociale. Sans commettre l’erreur assimilationist de les considérer l’un et l’autre comme identique, il est néanmoins possible de repérer l’émergence d’une Nation dans un environnement social, à côté des autres communautés nationales, l’ensemble constituant une Société Civile donnée. À la suite de cette reconnaissance mutuelle, il est indispensable de permettre la consolidation de l’identité de chacune des formations existantes dans cette société grâce à la garantie d’une représentation à l’Assemblée Constituante convoquée dans le but de renforcer la nouvelle Société indépendante.

Le Mouvement social et la Société Civile

Dans la société civile, le « Conseil Social » à l’état embryonnaire prend habituellement la forme d’un Rassemblement pour une alternative politique . On y voit alors les délégués des diverses tendances politiques et sociales s’organiser et se regrouper en fonction de leur nature et affinités respectives. Si la loi constitutionnelle de la société naissante parvient à trouver sa propre cohérence réciproque à travers la reconnaissance des formations qui en constituent la base, elle peut alors espérer réussir une révolution «tranquille » non-violente. Ceci implique cependant que le Conseil Social opère selon un principe essentiel, à savoir le Principe de réciprocité. (1) Et c’est celui-ci qui donne son sens au concept de Pluralisme. Ce concept a reçu son application la plus achevée dans l’autonomie nationale-culturelle selon Otto Bauer, théoricien du Parti Social-Démocrate viennois des années 20. Son projet de fédération statut cantonal, provincial ou bien municipal aux communautés nationales (ainsi qu’aux communautés sociales, ou formations sociales). Malheureusement ce projet ne vu jamais le jour, et d’ailleurs notre Peuple Juif n’était pas considéré comme une Nation. L’absence de reconnaissance du Peuple Juif comme Nation tient au fait que le droit à cette reconnaissance était monopolisé par les tenants d’une conception étatiste qui l’appliquèrent en dépit de l’existence d’autres conceptions. En effet l’État ne reconnaît habituellement qu’une seule Nation. On rencontre la même contradiction dans le cas du Canada — l’absence de reconnaissance du Québec ou des Québécois par l’État-Nation avec à sa tête la Reine d’Angleterre. Ce Dominion du Canada, cette Confédération, ou encore cette Union des Canadas comme on l’appelait, est incapable d’assimiler près du tiers de sa population alors qu’il le fait avec des nationalités moins nombreuses. Pour ce qui est de la Terre du Québec, elle n’inclut en fait que la majorité de la Nation Québécoise, pour peu qu’on aille au-delà des frontières de l’État. Il y a des millions de Québécois qui vivent dans les États américains du Vermont, du Massachusetts, de la Louisiane et de la Floride, de sorte qu’il serait plus approprié de nommer cette société civile Kébèk selon sa dénomination franco-Algonquin commune. Le Peuple des Kébécois/ses se trouve encore dans les provinces canadiennes elles-mêmes. Une autre nationalité appartenant à la société civile du Kébèk est le peuple Acadien du Nouveau Brunswick et de la Louisiane. En tout et pour tout, cette société civile francophone nord-américaine regroupe de 15 à 20 millions de personnes, comparés aux 7 millions dans la territoire de Québec.
La conception étatiste ne tient pas compte de l`existence de plus d’une culture dont témoigne la présence de langues autres que celles répandues. Si l’anglais est reconnu, avec les Lois 101 et 66, ce n’est pas le cas d’autres langues.
Au cours du processus par lequel cette Société s’instituera en tant que pays indépendant, la Convention constitutionnelle, ou Assemblée, se devra d’accueillir les délégués des différentes communautés nationales, sur la base d’une représentation proportionnelle, avec les autres formations sociales; ainsi serait formée l’Assemblée Constituante. L’application du Principe de Réciprocité conduit alors le processus qui mène à une Fédération de fédérations (2), dans une Société commune. Cette Société indépendante cherche ensuite à conclure des traités ayant force de loi commune avec d’autres Sociétés indépendantes semblables. Tel est le véritable sens de l’Inter-Nationalisme. La formation sociale qui entreprend d’accomplir un tel projet est donc tenue de respecter le but fixé et d’appliquer le même principe de réciprocité en reconnaissant toutes les formations sociales qui se considèrent comme des Nations, de quelque façon qu’elles se définissent. On légitime le sens qu’on donne à l’«autodétermination» en reconnaissant le même droit aux autres, le principe étant valable pour tous les membres de la Société. Ainsi donc, le Conseil Social et ses formations sociales naissantes doivent solliciter une représentation de chacune des communautés nationales. Les délégués des nationalités participeront donc de façon consensuelle à l`élaboration du cadre constitutionnel. (3) L’autonomie inhérente à chacune des formations nationales constituées se reflète dans l’autonomie des divers comités sectoriels qui forment ensemble un comité autonome des nationalités, celui-ci pouvant présenter des propositions au Comité de Coordination ou au Secrétariat pour qu’elles soient appliquées dans l’ensemble. Constitué de cette façon, un mouvement social aurait alors l’autorité d’interpeller l’État en place au nom de la Société Civile afin de contester l’appareil légal, créant une situation pré-révolutionnaire (l’opposition extraparlementaire). Conjointement à l’organisation politique dans sa dimension électorale et autre, la prédominance de la Société Civile en face de l’État dans une société indépendante serait ainsi assurée. Le programme électoral du Parti de la démocratie socialiste comporte le droit à l’autodétermination des Nations Autochtones, allant jusqu’à l’indépendance. En revanche, dans le cas du Parti Travailliste social-démocrate israélien a toujours subsisté une contradiction entre la reconnaissance de la nationalité israélienne et non de celle des autres nations, tels les Palestiniens. C’est un trait typique de la conception étatiste telle qu’elle est incarnée par l’État d’Israël. On ne s’étonnera pas dans ces conditions que le Parti Québécois considère l’ambassadeur d’Israël comme le représentant de la communauté juive. De toute évidence, cela ne laisse guère de chance à une reconnaissance locale de la nationalité juive en tant que telle par un État Indépendant du Québec. (4)

Parmi les autres limitations impliquées par la conception étatiste de l’Indépendance, mentionnons la proposition de conserver l’infrastructure économique de l’État Canadien, telle que la monnaie sous le contrôle de la Banque du Canada, l’Accord de Libre Échange Nord-Américain (ALÉNA), l’OTAN, le NORAD, les lois sur les privilèges corporatifs, le Code Criminel, et la Monarchie Britannique. Un Conseil Social traitera les conditions économiques aussi bien que politiques comme des priorités. Établi initialement comme Assemblée Constituante, le Conseil Social restera en place en tant que nouvelle Chambre Haute de l’appareil gouvernemental. Dans cette optique, l’embryonnaire Rassemblement pour l’alternative politique peut contribuer au processus de transformation sociale.

——–

1. L’application sérieuse de ce Principe est développée dans la dissertation;
La réciprocité et le nationalisme, 1990 par Abraham Weizfeld.

La présentation approfondie du sujet ici est complété dans ma Thèse doctorale:
NATION, SOCIÉTÉ ET L’ÉTAT:
LE RAPPROCHEMENT DES NATIONS PALESTINIENNE ET JUIVE.

2. LE PRINCIPE FÉDÉRAL,
(Du Principe fédératif et de la nécessité de reconstituer le parti de la révolution)
était premier proposé par Pierre Joseph Proudhon.

3. Dans l’effet l’organisation sociale trouvait actuellement dans la Peuple Socialiste Jamahiriha Arabe Libyen fondé 1969. (Cette théorie d’organisation sociale est nom le Troisième Théorie Universelle et définit une Société sans un gouvernement mais plutôt Assemblée d’un Gens fixant dehors ses frais propres autonome et influençant par les comités révolutionnaires d’activistes politiques.)

4. Durant cette dernière campagne électorale de 1998 mon nom était présenté sur le scrutin dans le Compte 60% Juif de D’arcy-McGee sur la part du Parti de la démocratie socialiste et le Chignon/Bund Juif (les révolutionnaire ouvriers Juifs socialistes échangé le mouvement syndicat et parti politique d’avant-guerre de l’est Europe). Parmi la nationalité Juive le mouvement Bundist contredisait les parties politiques zionists en considérant la population Juive comme un tout, et ne juste ses membres propres de parti qui constituaient pas la base de qu`appareil pre – État .

Actuellement mon travail est porté sur le groupe Organisation pour la libération du Peuple Juif (OLPJ-JPLO) comme un moyens à régénérer le mouvement Bund / Chignon Juif, dans la solidarité réciproque avec le mouvement révolutionnaire Palestinien.

PROGRAMME SOCIAL
ADDENDUM DU DOCUMENT POLITIQUE
NATIONS DANS LE CONTEXTE INTER-NATIONAL
Sumission par Abraham Weizfeld
13/04/1999 v2

1. Les communautés nationales

1.1 Reconnaissant qu’un indépendant Société Québécois est une formation pluraliste avec un Nation majoritaire Francophone Québécois,

1.2 et que la langue commune de discours est Française,

1.3 il est de plus reconnu ces langues de minorités sont les moyens opératoires de communication entre une nationalité de minorité particulière.

1.4 Considérant que les communautés nationales sont constituées comme telles dans des termes de leur soi-reconnaissance, que références à “minorités ou communautés culturelles”, “ethniques” ou autrement être considérées que descriptives des entités sociales données les plaçant et droits des communautés nationales.

1.5 En outre, il est réitéré ici que les indigène premières nations exercent leur droit autonome à autodétermination dans la Société constituée pour faire suite à la langue, instruction, économie, et territoire, jusqu’à et incluant le droit à indépendance.

1.6 Il est aussi reconnu que les communautés nationales exercent en général leur droit à autonome co-habitation dans la réciprocité avec le droit à l’autodétermination du Nation Québécois.

2. Structure Sociale

2.1 Considérant la nécessité de représentation sur la part du Société Civile Québécois, il devient nécessaire à établir une chambre supérieure dans l’appareil gouverner d’une Société indépendante qui réfléchit les intérêts de la population comme distingue des intérêts généré par L’état.

2.2 Reconnaissant que Société Civile est composée de divers corps qui ont été formés par les divers formations sociales, basés à classe, nation, genre, et génération spécifique,

2.3 que chaque formation aussi sociale retient son existence autonome dans la conjonction avec que de la Société à grand,

2.4 il devient nécessaire à former une Assemblée Sociale qui reçoit sa représentation des divers organisations représentant ces formations sociales,

2.5 que ces délégations sont formées sur une base proportionnelle, sont irrévocable, et responsables à leurs affiliations organisationnelles propres,

2.6 que ces délégués sont sélectionnés par l’élection populaire dans leur constituant formation sociale et corps organisationnel.

2.7 L’assemblée Sociale est initiée par la convocation d’une Assemblée Constitutionnelle qui formule les conditions de la constitution sociale et L’assemblée Sociale dans le particulier,

2.8 que la composition de l’assemblée constitutionnelle proposée correspond aux conditions présentée pour la formation de l’Assemblée Sociale,

2.9 et que les conclusions de cette assemblée relier sur l’appareil gouverner dans la perpétuité avec le recours à l’Assemblée Sociale,

2.10 et que les formulations proposées de la constitution sociale être ratifiées par le référendum populaire simultané dans les divers formations sociales autonomes.

2.11 De plus, que L’assemblée Sociale est constituée sur une régionale, classe, citoyen, genre et génération base spécifique comme une Assemblée Sociale Fondamentale,

2.12 que l’assemblée Sociale Fondamentale est assemblée sur une base autonome relativement à des intérêts spécifiques et une affectation proportionnelle des ressources sociales,

2.13 que L’assemblée Sociale Fondamentale sélectionne son Secrétariat à réaliser sa volonté collective,

2.14 avec le secrétariat fondamental devenant un constituant du secrétariat général formant lui-même exécuter la volonté de l’Assemblée Sociale Générale.

2.15 L’assemblée Sociale Générale réfère ses propositions pour des projets sociaux à la parlementaires gouvernant la structure pour la mise-en-oeuvre dans la loi, et les affectations budgétaires générales,

2.16 que les formulations proposées reçues du gouvernement être considérées par l’Assemblée Sociale Générale pour la révision, consultation ou confirmation.

3. Les formations organisationnelles

3.1 Considérant que le Parti de la démocratie socialiste (PDS – Parti de la démocratie-socialiste) est formé comme la représentation organisationnelle d’ouvriers, femmes et étudiants, il doit être attendu que certains de ses membres étaient parmi les fondateurs de l’organisation sociale Rassemblement pour une alternative politique (RAP) considérant l’opposition commune au neo-libérales partis politiques électorales PQ, PLQ, et l’ADQ-emd,

3.2 qu’en outre, le RAP retient le potentiel à former une assemblée sociale embryonnaire en représentant les intérêts de l’émergeant la société civile indépendante de Québec,

3.3 reconnaissant que le RAP est un hetrogenous formation organisationnelle, étant constitué ensemble avec autres formations politiques telles que le MQS (Mouvement pour une Québec Souverain) comme un front uni,

3.4 que le PDS entretiendra son existence organisationnelle comme un mouvement et parti politique indépendante,

3.5 il est approprié à formuler une stratégie électorale commune parmi les divers tendances politiques qui sont formés ou formés dans le RAP, affectant certaines comptes à une ou l’autre formation électorale si et quand possible dans l’sanctionnement réciproque .

-fin-

JNF “Jewish National Fund” A Summary and Critique

2013/11/30

Alliance of Concerned Jewish Canadians
Alliance de canadien-nes juif-juives concerné-es
A C J C

ACJC2006-subscribe@yahoogroups.com
http://groups.yahoo.com/group/ACJC2006
News/nouvelles &discussion List-e:
JUNITY-CANADA-subscribe@yahoogroups.com

~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~

2007-09-28

The Honourable Robert Douglas Nicholson
Minister of Justice and Attorney General of Canada
284 Wellington Street
Ottawa, Ontario K1A 0H8

RE: Ronald Saba submission on the JNF (Jewish National Fund)

To all concerned;

It is important to emphasize two points in support of the submission and presentation made by Ronald Saba in the complaint filed with respect to the Jewish National Fund. One point is that the name given by the JNF is not indicative of its identity. One should take note that in the Israel context it is given the Hebrew name Karen Kayemeth Leisrael (KKL) which actually means “Perpetual Fund / Capital for Israel”. Accordingly this organization is in effect as agency of the State of Israel and is not a Jewish communal institution of Canada. This point is elaborated in my summation of the origins of the JNF which is annexed here as Annex A: JNF Jewish National Fund: A Summary and Critique. Annex B is an AFFIDAVIT that testifies to these issues by direct observation. Annex C here following is my submission to the Canada Customs and Revenue Agency (Charities Division)
The second point to be made is that it is not entirely correct to designate the policy of the JNF as serving the interests of Jewish people who wish to settle on lands that are under its control in the State of Israel or otherwise in occupied Palestinian territories. The reason for this is that there is an additional criterion for the selection of prospective candidates for the leasing of such lands which is not stated as a matter of policy but is followed nonetheless in practice. That is the selection policy of requiring that the Jewish candidates also be considered politically appropriate to be offered the prospect of leasing the lands in question for a 48 year contract. The test of political correctness is based upon the implicit agreement to refuse access to such lands to the indigenous Palestinian population. The definitive case that has brought this policy to the open is that of Dr. Uri Davis, an Israeli citizen who sought to provide the tract of land that he leased for the use of a Palestinian colleague. This choice was considered to be in contradiction to the initial contract and was refused to be honoured. One is obliged to conclude that such lands are not available to those Jewish citizens who would seek to share their use of such lands with any Palestinian person. This is the definitive definition of social discrimination. The issue that is raised here in consequence is why such a practice is considered illegal in Israel itself by the Attorney General and not by the government of Canada or any of its provinces or by the appropriate institutions of Canadian civil society.

It would be appropriate to conclude that the pretext of the JNF being associated with the Canadian Jewish community is fallacious and irrelevant to the legal matter of discrimination that is proven. The failure to implement this categorization is in itself an act of complicity with the discriminatory practice in effect and the political criterion that is the motivating factor for such discrimination.

I would encourage all concerned to re-evaluate their stance in this issue to clear up any legal responsibility that would become operative in the light of such practices.

Yours truly,

___________________________________
Abraham Weizfeld

cc: Canadian Human Rights Commission
425 de Maisonneuve West
Montreal, Quebec H3A 3G5

Telephone: (514) 283-5218
Toll Free: 1-800-999-6899
TTY: 1-888-643-3304
Fax: (514) 283-5084

Jennifer Lynch, Q.C.
Chief Commissioner of the Canadian Human Rights Commission.
Canadian Human Rights Commission
344 Slater Street, 8th Floor
Ottawa, Ontario K1A 1E1
Canada

Commission des droits de la personne et des droits de la jeunesse du Québec
360, Saint-Jacques Street, 2nd floor
Montréal (Québec) H2Y 1P5
Canada

Alberta Human Rights and Citizenship Commission
Northern Regional Office
800 Standard Life Centre
10405 Jasper Avenue
Edmonton, Alberta T5J 4R7

Annex A

JNF “Jewish National Fund”
A Summary and Critique
June 4, 2007

The “Jewish National Fund” so-named by the nascent Zionist movement that was founded in 1897 remains as pillar in the construction that is now known as the State of Israel or in Hebrew as Medina Yisrael. At the founding Zionist Congress in Basel, Switzerland Hermann Schapira proposed the establishment of a fund to acquire territory under the authority of the Zionist State alone. Although it was to be acquired in the name of the Jewish People, these lands were never to be owned by the proposed residents themselves but rather granted leases for periods not exceeding 49 years. In this manner such lands became State acquisitions never to be sold to any other person, in particular the indigenous inhabitants themselves from which it was to be acquired. By 1882 the number of Jewish residents in Palestine was 24,000 out of a total population of about 550,000. Prior to the Zionist colonization the resident Jewish population of 10,000 were well integrated Palestinians. Even today there are 300 Jewish-Palestinian residents in the besieged city of Nablus.
The initial purchases of lands in the territory of Palestine, a province under the Ottoman Empire, resulted in minimal acquisitions. It was only after the December 1917 occupation of Jerusalem by British General Edmund Allenby that the JNF became a significant colonizing agency. In July 1920 the government of Palestine enacted an Immigration Ordinance and a Land Transfer Ordinance which led to the certification the JNF as “having purposes of public utility and thereupon registered as a foreign company”
The original funding agency of the JNF was incorporated in England in 1890 as the Jewish Colonial Trust (Juedishe Colonial Bank) Limited with all its shares held by the World Zionist Organization (WZO). This Bank has since become “The National Bank of Israel Ltd.” (Bank Leumi Le-Israel) in 1951 with 88% of its stock owned by the “Treasury for the Settlement of Jews, Ltd.” (Otsar Hityashvut ha-Yehudim BM), the Israeli successor company set up in 1955 to the English Jewish Colonial Trust of the WZO.
It should be noted that the English name for the JNF, Jewish Natioal Fund is found to be given the Hebrew name Karen Kayemeth Leisrael (KKL) which actually means “Perpetual Fund / Capital for Israel”. The association made with the Jewish identity is rather a convenience to secure the necessary political capital in order to establish the State itself. Ironically this phenomenon is reminiscent of the initial proposition by Oliver Cromwell to deport the British Jewish population to colonize Palestine as Anglicized Jews!

Summary by: Abraham Weizfeld, B.Sc., M.A., Ph.D. cand.
Administration Secretary Alliance of Concerned Jewish Canadians
saalaha@fokus.name 514.284.66.42

FNJ, le « Fonds national juif » :
un résumé et une critique
le 7 juin 2007

Le “Fonds national juif” (FNJ), ainsi nommé par le mouvement sioniste naissant fondé en 1897, demeure un pilier dans la construction de ce qui est maintenant connu comme l’État d’Israël ou, en hébreu, Medina Yisrael. Au congrès de fondation du mouvement sioniste à Bâle, en Suisse, Hermann Schapira a proposé l’établissement d’un fonds pour acquérir des terres sous la seule autorité de l’État sioniste. Bien que ces terres devaient être acquises au nom du peuple juif, elles ne devaient jamais être possédées par les éventuels résidents eux-mêmes, mais plutôt cédées en vertu de baux pour des périodes n’excédant pas 49 ans. Ces terres devenaient ainsi des acquisitions de l’État ne pouvant jamais être vendues à personne d’autre; en particulier, elles ne pourraient être vendues aux habitants indigènes eux-mêmes, de qui elles devaient être acquises. En 1882, le nombre de résidents juifs en Palestine était 24 000, sur une population totale d’environ 550 000. Avant la colonisation sioniste, la population juive locale, totalisant 10 000 personnes, était des Palestiniens et des Palestiniennes bien intégrés. Et aujourd’hui même, il y a 300 résidents juifs-palestiniens dans la ville assiégée de Naplouse.
Les premiers achats de terrains dans le territoire de la Palestine, une province sous l’Empire ottoman, n’ont représenté que des acquisitions minimes. C’est seulement après l’occupation de Jérusalem en décembre 1917 par le général britannique Edmund Allenby que le FNJ est devenu une agence de colonisation significative. En juillet 1920, le gouvernement de la Palestine a adopté une Ordonnance d’immigration et une Ordonnance de transfert des terres qui ont conduit à la certification du FNJ en tant qu’agence “ayant des buts d’utilité publique et conséquemment enregistrée comme compagnie étrangère”.1
La première agence de financement du FNJ a été incorporée en Angleterre en 1890 sous le nom de Jewish Colonial Trust (Juedishe Colonial Bank) Limited, toutes ses actions étant détenues par l’Organisation sioniste mondiale (OSM). En 1951, cette banque est devenue The National Bank of Israel Ltd (Bank Leumi Le-Israel) dont 88 % des actions étaient possédées par la Treasury for the Settlement of Jews, Ltd (Otsar Hityashvut ha-Yehudim BM), la compagnie israélienne qui a succédé, en 1955, au Jewish Colonial Trust britannique de l’Organisation sioniste mondiale.
Fait à noter, le nom anglais du FNJ, Jewish National Fund, s’est fait accoler le nom hébraïque Karen Kayemeth Leisrael (KKL), qui signifie « Fonds/Capital perpétuel pour Israël ». L’association faite avec l’identité juive est surtout utile pour garantir le capital politique requis pour établir l’État lui-même. Ironiquement, ce phénomène n’est pas sans rappeler la proposition initiale d’Oliver Cromwell de déporter la population juive britannique pour coloniser la Palestine en tant que Juifs anglicisés !

Résumé par : Abraham Weizfeld, B.Sc., M.A., candidat au doctorat
Secrétaire administratif de l’Alliance de Canadien/nes juif/ves concerné/es
saalaha@fokus.name 514.284.66.42
—————-
1 Voir la note #109, page 47, The Jewish National Fund par Walter Lehn avec Uri Davis, Kegan Paul International, Londres et New York, 1988.
2 Voir la note #40, Ibid,. page 20.
3 Voir la page 24, Ibid.

ANNEX B

AFFIDAVIT
from
Abraham Weizfeld B.Sc., M.A., Ph.D. cand. l’UQAM

Concerning the charitable organization status
of the Jewish National Fund
“Jewish National Fund (JNF) of Canada (Keren Kayemeth Le’Israel)”
BN/Registration # 107534877 RR0001

by the Canada Customs and Revenue Agency (Charities Division)

of the Government of Canada

2003-12-12

~ ~ ~ ~ ~ ~

This testimonial on my behalf as a witness to the nature of the project known as “Canada Park” is of concern to an individual such as myself in two facets; one is that as a Canadian citizen for which there is an association being made in practice, and for the historical record, with Canada, a legal responsibility which is contrary to international law and contrary to the practice and policy of the various Canadian governments that have sat in office during the duration of this project’s existence. Secondly, as a Jewish-identified person I wish to file my objections to an act of “ethnic-cleansing”, as it is referred to currently, that has been conducted in the name of the national-cultural community to which I adhere, the Jewish People. It is my ardent wish that the Jewish People shall not be identified with the collective human-rights crimes of the State of Israel which have been implicated by the claims of the Zionist political parties to assert the legitimacy of the Jewish People as a justification of that particular militarist project.. In addition it is my wish that this country’s reputation should not be tarnished by the name given to the lands confiscated to become the “Canada Park” that is the pride of the Canadian Jewish National Fund, the registered charitable organization having claimed the “Canada Park” project as a registered tax-deductible receipt donation recipient on the part of the Charities Division of the Customs and Revenue Agency. Even though the local agency which implemented the “Canada Park” may be registered as a charitable donation under Israeli State law, the criteria for such a registration is in contradiction with the law as it is know in Canada, as well as international law and as well as again in terms of the UNGA & SC resolutions.
The object of this inquiry may seem innocuous at first sight, since it takes the form of a public park, however this case example is indicative of the entire set of relations between the Palestinian People-Nation and the legal entity called the State of Israel, since the acquisition of the land in question is part and parcel of the vast territories that were acquired by military means during the occupation of 1967. Although I have listened to many explanations of why this particular event was legitimatised by the act of war by another State neighbouring the State of Israel, I nonetheless cannot accept the connection between a minor border-waterway dispute and the occupation and retention of vast areas of land then known as the West Bank of the Jordan river, in addition to a strip of land in the Gaza that was part of the Sinai peninsula that was under the authority of the State of Egypt, and is now once again. The area now known as “Canada Park” is part of the territories which were occupied and retained in the events of 1967. I must reiterate that my questioning of the status of this land is furthermore based upon the unacceptability of the Nineteenth Century practice that was based upon what was called the “right of conquest”, a phrase that is often invoked but never verified in justification of the use of the lands in question.
In practical terms occupation and retention of the land in question means many different and varied practices and the most significant of which is the displacement of the indigenous residents who were present in the lands of “Canada Park” and had established three villages over a lengthy period of time. In my visit of this area it was obvious that there is overwhelming evidence of the presence of the villages that had persisted there over a very lengthy period of time. Close to the entranceway to the “Park” are the remains of some of the houses that have stood in one of the villages in which all that remained were the foundation stones in close proximity. The nature of the stones as well is indicative of the age of the villages which appear to be many hundreds of years old at the very least. The building stones of the various ages are evident in terms comparable to the Jerusalem wall stones that are weather-beaten to the degree of more than 2000 years and perhaps even older as well if one happens to be in the proximity of the original stone-works of the Jebusite People who established the city some 3500 years ago, not to mention the even older stones still in operation in the buildings and walls of the town of Akko which is some 5000 years old. The stones that are in evidence in the “Canada Park” village were closer in age to the Jerusalem stones and not at all comparable to ordinary building materials. This is the indication of the prior rights and seniority involved in terms of the ownership and legal authority for these particular lands.
The evidence that these villages were in fact operative and peopled by Palestinian nationals is provided by the descendents of those people themselves. In particular there is the Dr. El-Deep who has sought to compile not only his and other family’s accounts of their dispossession, as well as their legal documentation and house keys with which I have become familiar with since being given the opportunity to observe these proofs. However besides these tangible proofs there is also the documentary images in photographs that have been presented in conference here in Montréal recently at the University of Concordia during the course of the Polanyi conference. Dr. El-Deep presented the enlarged photographs of the events in 1967 during the expulsion of the inhabitants of Imwas, Yalu, and Bayt Nuba in the West Bank. These are photographs taken by an Israeli soldier during the events and provide a second dimension of proof as to the inhabitants of the villages.
Taking into consideration the various proofs available, I was struck to see the monument that had been erected as walls carrying metal plaques with the names of Canadians engraved there as donors to the Canadian branch of the Jewish National Fund which was publicly designated as the sponsor of the “Canada Park” project at the entrance to the area contained a children’s playground, picnic tables, trees and the monument. The monument in particular is significant since it is made of the same stones that are to be found in the ruins of the Palestinian villages at their original sites not far away. The stones are evidently of the same materiel, same colouration, the same cut (cubed) and obviously of the same weather-beaten age.
I would here submit the actual photographs that I myself was able to take of both the stone foundations of the Palestinian village and the stone walls that had been constructed of the homes that were destroyed.

1. Village stones and monument

2. Stone-wall monument of JNF site (“Canada Park”)

3. JNF entrance sign to “Canada Park”

There is a further aspect to this affair that is a matter of personal acquaintance and even family relation who first brought my attention to this project of “Canada Park”. When the inauguration of the project was accomplished, there were a number of the donors who came to attend the opening ceremonies. I remember hearing of the event from my cousin who was in attendance since her husband was one of the listed major donors. It was a visit during which it was said that one could see the plaques with the name of the donors fixed onto a wall of stones, which was very beautiful. I asked, at that time, where the stones had come from and the response moved to centre on the subject of some ancient Roman stone carvings that had been strewn about the corner gardens that were part of the monument fixtures. Evidently the response was not aware of where the stone cubes in the walls came from and so assumed that they were of the Roman era.
As it may be supposed from this exposition submitted, there is a certain degree of misconception that has been established concerning this project and I would ask you’re the seriously considered opinion of the Charities Division to consider the legal standing of this project and its sponsor here in Canada. Since there may very well be a degree of negligence involved here is such a sponsorship it would inappropriate for the government of Canada to be implicated in such a venture especially when Canada cold play a significant role the developing period of international diplomacy that is upon us. Not only would it help Canada to gain a further degree of diplomatic stature, such a re-evaluation of the JNF registration would also enable Canada to exert a certain influence in the current status of the 1967 occupied territories. Additionally it is a legal responsibility of the government agencies of Canada to consider the legal implications for Canada itself if such a legal link is not annulled otherwise leading to the appearance of complicity in the legal infractions involved. These of course are all legal issues that are currently part and parcel of the current series of negotiations. At the very least such complicity could strain the possible relations that Canada has with the diplomatic relations with such a body as the recognized Palestine Embassy in Ottawa as well as various United Nations agencies resulting in the loss of opportunities that Canada currently seeks to fulfill in the prospects for peace in the “Middle East”. It is noteworthy that this concern is becoming of interest to many Canadians who have presented themselves in public just this past winter to demonstrate their abhorrence of the resort to militarism when negotiations are entirely possible to resolve the existing disputes.
Thus I submit here the reasons that I am able to present for your consideration in this vital matter which concerns the best hopes of Canadians, the Palestinians and the majority of the Jewish people who have chosen to not even be legally represented by the State of Israel, being residents and citizens of other States where we have chosen to fulfill our lives and hopes for peace.

Signed in Montréal the 12 / 12 / 2003

_________________________________________
Abraham Weizfeld

Annex C

Concerning the charitable organization status
of the Jewish National Fund
by the Canada Customs and Revenue Agency (Charities Division)
of the Government of Canada

2003-11-08
By Abraham Weizfeld
~ ~ ~ ~ ~ ~
Introduction:

This submission arising from Jewish individual academics addresses the distinction that we wish to make between the specific organizational representative, the Jewish National Fund (JNF), and the Jewish community as a whole which remains independent of such activities despite claims to the contrary.

Founding principles of the JNF:

The specifications for “The Jewish Company” are the founding clauses of the JNF and the work of Theodor Herzl “The Jew’s State’ constitute its founding document giving rise to the State of Israel including the JNF agency in Canada. As specified “its functions are not confined to the colonial sphere.” The Jewish Company … the English legal sense, under the laws and protection of England.”, which is precisely where the JNF was first incorporated.
The characteristics defining “The Jewish Company” reflect the precise functions of the JNF, that is, “In the new country it is the Jewish Company which will organize economic activity.” Reference is made to the various sites from which the “Jewish Company would operate from each legal jurisdiction; “colonization companies* — a Jewish Chartered Company.”
What distinguished the doctrine of Herzl was its departure from the utopian projections of the Hegelian type of the time and became a revolutionary construction outside of the bounds of simple practicability. The first of these constructions was “The Jewish Company” and it was soon after incorporated as the JNF.
The defining legal character of “The Jewish Company” was defined precisely in the terms; “The vast profits from the land speculation will flow in their entirety into Company coffers, because it has a right to unlimited profits like every free entrepreneur.” thus marking a fundamental distinction from a charitable organization. Herzl continues, “Rather, the founders and directors of the Jewish Company should be offering a good business deal …” The purpose of the organization as a whole is summarized as; “In this way it can become a historically exemplary form of colonization and state formation, with unprecedented chances of success.”
This form of activity is to be distinguished from the efforts made by certain Jewish philanthropists who sought to provide a lieu for the poorest of the Jewish communities to find the opportunities to rise above the misery of ghetto life in some other lieu other than their own countries of activity and residence. As the translator and editor of Herzl’s work Henk Overberg comments in his introduction;
Baron Maurice de Hirsch, whom Herzl went to see in Paris on 2 June 1895 as he was writing The Jews’ State, was a perfect representative of this tradition. Edmond de Rothschild, whom Herzl called “the philanthropic Zionist,” and with whom he had a long meeting was another example. Both these men were sounded out by Herzl to see whether their philanthropy could be stretched to political support for a new state for Jews. Both these encounters remained without immediate practical issue. Pg. 19.
The nature of “The Jewish Company” is furthermore defined within the context of the project as whole for which it was conceived. Functioning in the international context it was nonetheless conceived as an extraterritorial entity which was given the characteristics of State sovereignty apart from the State structure within which it was incorporated and constituted. This feature is stated explicitly;

At any rate the Jews’ State is conceived as a quite unique new phenomenon attached to an as yet undecided territory. But a state is not constituted of pieces of land; rather, a group of people gathered under a sovereignty make up a state.

“The Jewish Company” then is integral to the pre-State conditions necessary for the formation of such a State and is constituted as sovereignty independent of the legal authority under which this company seeks to incorporate itself and furthermore seeks to conduct itself as a private enterprise and not a charitable organization.
The nature of “The Jewish Company” as projected by Theodor Herzl the principal founder of the Zionist movement of 1897, then is conceived and formulated as a Statist formation whose sole purpose is to promote and prepare the conditions for the establishment of the State as conceived by this particular political tendency. This enterprise then is the corner stone of the sovereign Sate projected to be coming into existence. Its purpose is none other than to acquire the resources to lay claim to the territory that is to form the site for such a State. “In the new country it is the Jewish Company which will organize economic activity.”
The exclusivity of the venture is specified quite clearly as being the accumulation of land and guarded as the possession of one People alone so that it may not be purchased in turn by any members of the local inhabitants in return.
As such its nature is exclusive and includes the dispossession of the local inhabitants of such territory.
* * *